ETHICS INDEPENDENT OF
RELIGION
CONTENTS
PAGE NUMBER
In pdf in htm
Preface
2 2
Philosophy
in general
3 3
Epistemology
9 5
Metaphysics
14 7
Philosophical
elements in general ethics 26 10
Descriptive
ethics
38 13
Particular
ethical norms
45 15
Process of
ethical evaluation and decision making 56 18
Ethics and
the philosophy of India
71 23
Ethics and
the philosophy of China
83 26
Bibliography
100 31
PREFACE
In
Santa Cruz Spirituality, Chapter 5
Particulars, I noted that ÒLastly, all forms of spirituality are to their
possessors a guide to the way they should act in the world. In other words, there is a connection
between spirituality and morality.Ó
Many religions contain a detailed moral code which not only serves as a
basis for civil law, but also permeates the thinking of a society to the extent
that the citizens can hardly conceive of a morality that is not based on
religion. Nevertheless,
philosophers of all ages have done just that: they have treated what they
usually term Ethics, the study of how
people should act and even of the rewards or punishments for their
actions. To understand
philosophical ethics one must begin by knowing what philosophy is and what it
has to say about human nature and about the world as a whole. It follows that a creditable treatment of philosophical ethics begins
with at least a summary of
philosophy and of the steps leading to ethics properly understood. The present essay undertakes to
summarize philosophy sufficiently to meet this requirement. It consists of excerpts from, actually
most of, a work entitled Ethics as
Philosophy, which I wrote before Santa
Cruz Spirituality and copyrighted in 2004.
The
first seven chapters of this study are in the traditional manner in which
Western philosophy is presented. The particular way they are organized reflects
the Thomistic philosophy which I studied many years ago to earn the PhD degree
in philosophy at the Pontifical Gregorian University of the Vatican City The issues, however, are by and large
universal, and they exist also in Eastern philosophy, as will be shown in the
briefer account of ethics in the philosophy of India and China in the final two
chapters.
PHILOSOPHY
IN GENERAL
Definition of Philosophy
The
things that can be said about philosophy can be classed under three headings:
its definition, its relation to similar activities, and its divisions. These
headings relate to the phases of the observation of anything, that is,
inspecting it, inspecting its relation to similar things (which may include
results or consequences of its actions), and inspecting its components (however
they may compose it).
As
a process philosophy consists of an exercise of reasoning or reflection. It is concerned with what we think
rather than with what we feel; it is intellectual and not affective
or emotional. By various
processes of thinking such as analysis and synthesis, deduction and induction,
philosophy develops sets of statements about the world as a whole and about the
place of people in it. The
statements express systematic answers to the broad questions, what?, whence?
whither? how (i.e., by what means)? why ( i.e., to what end, if any)?, about
the world in general or specifically about humankind. It is by no means clear that there are answers to all the
general questions that people can pose about themselves and the world, but
history shows that people cannot be prevented from asking them and attempting
to answer them by themselves, that is, by thinking about them.
These
broad (also called ÒultimateÓ) questions themselves evolve with the attempt to
answer them, and can be considered as the results of our lines of inquiry as
well as interrogatives.
A
term I introduced here and which calls for explanation is
"world". By
"world" I refer to the whole of whatever exists. At this point there is no concern for
how it exists or even for what "existence" itself means. Both ÒworldÓ and ÒexistenceÓ can be
talked about, but they are ÒgivensÓ that cannot be defined by some referent
extraneous to themselves.
In
philosophy as a process knowledge about the world is taken as the data from
which the answers mentioned above are extracted. Thus philosophy derives from pre-existing knowledge, and its
value depends on the accuracy of this knowledge. A philosophy about the physical universe, for example, that
accepts as data the centrality of the earth is going to be blind to many
insights that become possible through a more scientific cosmology.
Knowledge
is taken here to be an integration of data with some degree of insight into the
significance, the meaning, or the workings of whatever the data are about. Understanding is another word we
shall use, and we take it to be stronger than knowledge: we have to know
something well before we can understand it.
"The
pursuit of wisdom" is an apt description of philosophy if wisdom is taken
to mean consummate understanding of all that is important to human life. Wise persons, that is, have come to at
least some answers to the basic questions, are secure in the answers, and are
in a position to teach them to others.
As far as I know, all cultures have wise persons and honor them. Their fellow members of the culture do
not necessarily expect them to know all the answers to all questions, but they
do esteem them for knowing the answers to the important questions, the ones
that count.
In
addition to philosophers there are thinkers - ÒintellectualsÓ and essayists,
for example - who ponder the deeper aspects of particular problems or who
speculate generally but not systematically about the nature of things and their
reasons. Furthermore, human cultures have pre-scientific and non-religious
explanations of the world and their place in it. None of this is philosophy unless it reaches such a degree
of abstraction that it is systematic.
The product of this rigorous process is philosophy as a body of
knowledge, an object of study in itself.
Of all the cultures of the world only a few have reached the stage of
producing philosophy, and these, which are strung geographically along a line
from the Mediterranean Sea to the Yellow Sea, have been contributing to the
worldÕs patrimony of philosophy for about 2,500 years. The stories, myths, and legends of all
the rest contain many philosophical insights, but they are not philosophy.
In
"Identity and the Question of African Philosophy" Robert Birt reviews
a number of current opinions concerning African philosophical endeavors,
especially those in the past. He
makes it clear that those who require that philosophy be only that which is
done by professional academic philosophers of Western culture ask too much of
non-literate philosophical thinking, which certainly forms part of traditional
African cultures. Nevertheless, it
is true that Òone finds more literate African philosophizing in the past thirty
years than in the previous thirty centuries.Ó (p. 103) The works which Birt is
reviewing make no reference whatsover to the philosophies of India and
China.
Philosophy and Activities
Related to it
The
philosophic method of inspection and reflection noted above is similar to the
scientific method. In both there
is a process of searching, groping, speculating, but there are important
differences between the two processes.
Basically, of course, science begins with the observation of the
macrophenomena and microphenomena of the world, but philosophy starts with
knowledge that has already been scientifically gained. (It is said that induction is
the reasoning method of science whereas deduction is that of philosophy,
but this distinction no longer seems as clear-cut and useful as it formerly
did, and is probably not a useful way to compare philosophy with science.)
Another
key difference between philosophic and scientific method has to do with
hypothesis formulating and testing.
Both methods include these two phases, although philosophic hypothesis
stating is apt to be more linguistically diffuse and the methods of testing
differ markedly. Along with the
hypothesis science sets up a way to verify it, and each verified hypothesis
constitutes a block of knowledge which, presumably, has some practical value
and which leads to the construction of further hypotheses. There is, however, no such chain in
philosophic method. Philosophic
hypotheses are strictly explanations, that is to say, clarifications or
interpretations of the philosophic data, and there is no way to test them aside
from their own explanatory power.
(Obviously, various ones can be compared and contrasted among themselves.) Scientists who cross over the line between
verifiable to non-verifiable hypotheses have become ipso facto
philosophers.
The
non-verifiable aspect of philosophical statements leads many people who are
steeped in the scientific method to claim that philosophy not only makes
statements which cannot be verified, but also that these statements are
meaningless or devoid of content.
The philosopher replies to this that to have a meaning is not the same
as to be verifiable, and in particular that the philosophersÕ answers to the
basic questions mentioned above are neither verifiable nor falsifiable by the
scientific method. We do find that
gradually many questions which used to be answered philosophically now find
scientific answers. The
philosopher welcomes this progress and uses it to direct his or her attention
away from useless questions to useful ones, which stand out in sharper relief
because of the improved scientific knowledge which serves as a basis for the
philosophic enterprise.
There
remains one element important for a comparison of philosophy and science. Science positively and aggressively
acknowledges only one source of human knowledge, that which enters through the
senses, is quantifiable, and is manipulated by logical reasoning. According to some, philosophy builds
only on knowledge gained by this source, but according to others, there is also
intuitive knowledge which knows some things about the world directly,
without the intermediary of the senses.
How much this kind of knowledge can be manipulated by reasoning and
quantified is a further philosophic question. Science, on its own principles, cannot know whether there is
or is not such a thing as intuition.
Philosophy
also is closely related to art and religion. Each of these three is a way of describing the world, a
language, if you like, but the three diverge in their viewpoints on the world,
in their symbols for representing it, and in their affective experience of
it. Philosophy is the least
affective of the three, but even it often implies a way of life which is a
broad affective state. It does not
use many symbols beyond language, and it communicates only with a small
minority of people because of the difficulty it has in expressing itself in the
way that it must. Religion, for its part, is heavy with symbolism, is highly
affective, communicates in one way or the other with most of the world's
population, and it considers itself a guide to experiencing that which is
totally unknowable and inexpressible.
Art is symbolism.
Its many forms involve many kinds of affective response ranging from
pure esthetic experience to rich passion, and it reaches all the world's
population, although in extremely varied forms. Its subjects are not only immensely varied, but they are
treated in an astonishing variety of ways.
Philosophy,
religion, and art are related, and they are greatly intermingled, but the most
difficult distinction to be made among them is between philosophy and
religion. At the risk of
oversimplifying the distinction between the two we can pay attention to two
further differences which have a bearing on the present line of thought.
1)
Religion traces itself to a foundation of religious experience, an
intuition of beings, forces, or values that imposes itself on people either
directly, or through the intermediary of teaching by someone who does have
it. The relationship between this
intuition and the non-scientific intuition mentioned above is one of the
questions of both philosophy and religion. Generally, however, it is asserted that the intuition of religious experience
is transmitted to people from powers which transcend them whereas the
non-scientific intuition spoken of in regard to philosophy is thought to arise
from the human mind itself. (Religious
experience as an affective phenomenon is scrutinized in the famous works, The
Varieties of Religious Experience by William James and The Idea of the
Holy by Rudolf Otto.
Obviously, as an affective phenomenon religious experience can be
studied scientifically, whereas religious intuition as a form of knowing is not
within the range of scientific study.) (The role of language, not just
as a vehicle of communication concerning religious experience, but also as an
integral part of it, is dealt with by Ben-Ami Scharfstein in his Ineffability. Although religious experience is
ScharfsteinÕs focus, he also deals with the non-religious, non-scientific
intuition just mentioned.
Furthermore, he writes from the perspective of comparative religion and
philosophy rather than from a mere Western background.)
2)
Religion is more serious than philosophy is. Philosophy discourses about matters which are serious, but
which are not all vital to human life.
Religion, on the contrary, is exclusively about matters which are
proposed to be of great importance and concern. As such it lends itself to shared societal forms with
ethical codes.
I
developed these comparisons in a paper entitled "Microcomputers as
Philosophical Tools," which I presented at the Midyear Conference of the
American Society for Information Science in Bloomington, Indiana, 1984. As I gathered ideas for the paper the comparisons seemed to come
to me spontaneously, but when I went to write the paper I realized that I had
read an article which proposed something similar to it. Unable then to locate the article, I completed
the ASIS presentation, claiming neither that it was nor that it was not my
idea. I did, however, show a chart
which I myself had devised. It was
this:
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
COMPARISON OF ART, PHILOSOPHY, AND RELIGION
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
--------------------------------- BASIC DIRECTIONS -------------------------------------
Phen- Value of personal experience Intrepretation
of trans Oneness
of the world
om- personal
experience
enon
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Personal
experience can Some
people succeed in Although
no single
perceive
more than utility communicating
their artistic medium
of human art
in
objects and actions: it sees insight
to others by their can
refer to the whole
ART form, beauty, and
emotional art. Many people thus world,
the media taken
value. Such sight and sometimes
share the same conjointly
produce the
feeling
refer to natural perception
and feeling perception
of a world
and
artificial wholes and simultaneously
or unified
in the endless
to
excerpts from wholes. successively. possibilities
of its
own
forms.
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
The
human mind can pose Philosophical
reflection All
philosophies find
for
itself questions which leads
to a number of elements
which are
are
unrelated to everyday people
holding common common
to the whole
PHIL- living, but which refer so worldviews
and ideals world
and which unify
OS- significantly
to living and to with
consequent low it;
they find aspects
SOPHY the world that man feels com- intensity,
shared under
which the endless
pelled
to seek answers to emotions. parade
of phenomena
them,
and then to regulate his are
more one than many.
actions
by these answers.
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Some
people have exper- Religious
experience All
religions interpret
ience,
more or less intense, is
felt to be shared the
world as some kind
that
there is directly by
other persons and to of
transcendental
RELI- communicated to them be
communicable by one,
of which man
GION transcendental meaning means
of shared symbols. partakes
in some way.
about
the world and its
source
and about their
own
lives.
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
The divisions of philosophy
"Kant
himself summarized the main interest of philosophy in the four questions: What
can I know? What ought I do? What
may I hope for? What is man?"
(Martin, General Metaphysics, p. 201, referring to Kant's Logik,
Einleitung III). It is common for
expositions of Western philosophy to begin with questions such as Kant raises
and similar ones. By no means do
the philosophers all proceed in the same order, and I will propose the
questions here in an order which, I think, represents their interrelationship
clearly.
First
we ask about the validity of our human knowledge, and this includes the topics
of what is truth?
and how do we go about thinking accurately? The term epistemology is used
for the more speculative aspects of this philosophy of knowledge, and
its techniques of application are the various forms of logic.
Having
established to our satisfaction that human knowledge is valid at least to some
knowable extent, we look at the world.
First at the whole of it. That is, we ask, what can be said about
everything there is and anything there could be? The notion of a general study of being is a rather daunting
one to people who are accustomed to fractionalizing knowledge into the various
sciences and who see a Grand Unified Theory of Everything exclusively as a
function of subatomic physics.
Nevertheless, the philosophy of being , which is also called ontology,
has a secure place in the world of philosophers.
The
general study of ontology leads us in three specific directions:
1)
is there a supreme being, and if so what can be said about such? This is often called natural
theology.
2) what else can be said about the
observable world: how it came to be, what can be said about anything and
everything in it, and what can be said of its fate? This can be called general
philosophy of the observable world.
The terms "cosmogony" and "cosmology" (more properly
"philosophical cosmogony" and "philosophical cosmology")
have been used to name this branch of philosophy, but they are currently out of
favor among philosophers, although scientists use them in their accounts of the
observable world. Aside from the
terms used, philosophy of the world is not a prime concern of contemporary
philosophers. Still, it is not
completely lacking, as can be shown by philosophical treatment of the immediate
world of human experience, the environment, as we shall encounter in the
section on environmental and ecological ethics under Special Questions of
Ethics.
Process
and Reality by Alfred North Whitehead (New York: Harper and Row, 1960.
First published in 1929.) is a true philosophical cosmology. Against a background of post Newtonian
physics Whitehead discourses about the perennial questions of metaphysics: the
one / the many, flux / stasis, actual / potential, being / becoming, eternity /
time, God / world. Although
explicitly mentioning the weakness of the human mind, he proposes that
syntheses of these opposites are possible within the limits of our
understanding. The flow of his
thought is quite clear, although the points along the way are obscured by the
esoteric terminology which he invents for the sake of explanation. It appears me that there is little to
be said about metaphysical cosmology outside of what Whitehead says in this
work and that he says it (making allowance for the terminology) as well as it
can be said. While the work
centers on cosmology, it reaches far into ontology and natural theology, but
very little into philosophy of people and society.
3)
What about people: what is it
to be a human being? what is human freedom? is there a special fate for humans? This can be called philosophy of people and society,
and it has been called "philosophy of man" and even "philosophical
anthropology." In spite of
the fact that the name for it is not entirely satisfactory, it exists in
treatments of human freedom and in all those essays, books, lectures, and
courses which, with greater or lesser employment of philosophical tradition,
tell us about ourselves.
Ontology
and the specific directions within it constitute traditional speculative
philosophy, i.e., speculation on "the nature of things," including
humans. Such speculation is
sometimes termed "metaphysics," and it is in this sense that we shall
use the word metaphysics. We will
return to this topic below under its own heading
With
a foundation in epistemology and metaphysics the philosopher can go on to
consider various fields. There are
philosophies of religion, of history, of politics; there are aesthetics and
ethics. The only one of these
which is of concern to us is ethics, the philosophy of human action. This scrutiny of the appropriateness of
human actions is a prominent field of human speculative endeavor in our
time. Although many efforts have
been made to develop ethics without relating it to epistemology and
metaphysics, traditionally it has been considered a branch of philosophy, and
this is the way we will proceed.
EPISTEMOLOGY
Postulates and Reasoning
Although
some knowledge and its validity are derived from other knowledge by processes
of reasoning, not all knowledge can be so justified. Some knowledge
has to be basic. Various
philosophical explanations of which knowledge comes first have been made, and
they all have in common the experience of the human observer. Accordingly, we postulate acceptance of
the observing subject who is not the whole of its observed object and who has
some accurate knowledge of the same.
This way of putting it rejects only radical skepticism, which has a
perennial appeal, but which deprives of value all intellectual discourse,
including discourse about itself.
As Nozick points out, attempts to refute skepticism do not satisfy the
skeptic; better we should learn from the skeptic how to be cautious in trusting
what we think we know. (Philosophical
Explanations, chapter 3)
A
further postulate, linked to that of the observer, is that of multiple
observers and of communication between them by means of language. The mere presence of multiple objects
in the world would not entail a multiplicity of observers, but the interchange
of language shows that some other entities are observing as I am and that we
can discourse about ourselves and about our observations
Language
is an imperfect vehicle of communication, which, by following its own rules,
can make absurd statements. Thus,
"This statement is meaningless," "I never tell the truth,"
or even "No truthful statement can be made" are not only
grammatically correct (even "All triangles are hot" is grammatically
correct), but they link concepts which are related. The strengths and weakness of language are topics of great
concern in contemporary philosophical and scientific activity. A century ago positivism, scientific
reductionism and the quantification of logic led such outstanding philosophers
as Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein and others of the School of British
Analytic Philosophy to minute analyses of language, its function and its
limits. Now much of this has been
tempered by the still more advanced and mature analyses of contemporary
philosophers. The core lesson of
Analytic Philosophy, however, is never to be out of the minds of philosophers: use
extreme caution to anchor words in reality. In these notes I am trying to be careful in the use of
language. To some extent this
simply involves the clear significations of words and the avoidance of unverifiable statements, but in
addition to this, we must recognize two age-old dangers to philosophers in
their use of language, which are (1) that of mistaking metaphor for reality and
(2) that of mistaking description for analysis. As far as I can see, (1) is a particular pitfall of inchoate
philosophies, such as that of the Pre-Socratics and the Pre-Confucians as well
as of Hegelianism and (2) is a defect shared by such otherwise diverse
philosophies as Scholasticism, Bergsonianism, and Existentialism.
Hilary
Lawson, in Closure A Story of
Everything , states that
"It is through closure that openness is divided into things."
(p. 3) Also, "The product of closure,
material, does not describe openness for there is a remainder, a residue that
is not exhausted by the material.
A remainder or residue that is almost everything. For in holding that
which is different as the same, or in holding one or more pieces of material -
one or more things - as another, there remains that which is different.... The remainder not exhausted by material
is not anything in particular, it is open, but the manner in which it is open
is influenced by the material.
This remainder will be referred to as 'texture'". (pp. 11-12)
Openness
- closure - things - material - texture
are LawsonÕs key, interlocking concepts. He intends to operate within a post-kantian, post analytic
philosophical context. But by
stating that closure and the associated activities apply to absolutely
everything, including reflexively closure itself, he joins the ranks of those
whose think that an overall description of reality is an analysis of it. His concepts are close to the act and
potency etc. of the scholastics.
Too bad, for he missed the opportunity to reason from the atemporally
undifferentiated to the object-world of Western philosophy. When I read the review of this in the
Times Literary Ssupplement of March 1, 2002 I thought perhaps he was coming
from the Chinese worldview, but nothing in the book as much as hints that he
knows about this!
In
view of our gradually improving understanding of how our minds come to know the
world, we realize that there are three historically well-known epistemological
theories which can no longer be sustained: 1) naive realism, which supposes that the world exists
exactly as we perceive it with our senses; 2) pure rationalism, which supposes that all being is
intelligible, i.e., that no being can exist unless we are capable of
understanding it, or, again, that the world of the mind is an exact
representation of the world outside the mind; 3) idealism, which does not acknowledge the existence of a
world outside the mind. Presented
in its extreme versions, each of these three theories has long since been
discredited, but each at least represents a phase of philosophical
understanding.
The
interplay between the above three positions was treated, throughout most of the
history of Western philosophy, as a metaphysical question, but that was before
it became necessary to distinguish epistemology from metaphysics. For the most part, the inclusion of
this matter in epistemology needs no explanation since Kant, but there are those
who still maintain that the prime concern of ontology is, how does the general
exist? and which is more real, the general or the particular? The best example for modern minds of
the meaningfulness of this question is its application to us humans: which is
more real, the individual or society?
(Premoderns would have phrased it, which is more real, individual human
beings or mankind?) Only
extremists are willing to answer that question when it is asked in these terms.
In
this framework Gottfried Martin proposes in General Metaphysics Its Problems
and its Method that there are three known (although there could, he says,
be more) positions on the matter, Plato's, Aristotle's, and Kant's. The being of the general is
respectively Idea, law of nature, and activity of thought (which threesome was
seen by Hegel) (p. 329). The first
to ask what being means was Plato, in the Sophist (p. 36). In the 20th century the formalism of
Hilbert, the logicism of Russell, and the intuitionism of Brouwer were
"intimately connected" with respectively the same philosophers (p.
328). Each of the three positions
has strengths and weaknesses; each is an incomplete approach to understanding,
each leads to aporias (insoluble puzzles), none reduces to the other, and none
prevails. (An aporia of Aristotle:
forms are present only in real beings - an imaginary being or limit-being {such
as justice} cannot have a form, and thus is unintelligible (p. 248). Also, the process of our receiving the
forms, species intelligibilis etc,. worked out by the Scholastics, is not
satisfying.) Others he mentions in
this context are Descartes, Leibnitz (at length) and Hegel, who thought,
unwisely, that the difficulties in reconciling the three positions could be
overcome by pushing the dialectical method (which is in each of the three to
some extent) to the extreme.
The
position which states that only concrete, singular, entities are real at all is
called nominalism, and it would almost seem that nominalism holds sway
in modern thinking in asmuch as singular, concrete entities are the units with
which science builds its theoretical structures. Thus nominalism is not incompatible with the study of sets
and classes from a logical-mathematical point of view. Of course we can view the world as the
raw data for sets and classes of our own devising, and this logico-mathematical
approach works functionally, enabling scientists, engineers, logicians, and
literary deconstructionists to communicate among themselves. The existence of a set or class, however,
does not explain why its elements belong to it. The explanation lies in the common characteristics of the
elements: what is it that makes them common, and the possible answers to this
question throw us back to the original question of how the mind works and how
it relates to external reality. It
appears to me that amidst the debris of discarded methods for answering this
question there is a modern one, systems theory, which does justice both to
scientific knowledge and philosophical tradition, and I will devote some space
to this under Questions of Ontology: questions of the philosophy of being.
Rationalism
can be considered possible only if human thought is completely and unfailingly
accurate in its interpretation of the world. A discovery of modern linguistics, however, is that various
natural languages interpret the world in markedly different ways. In languages which do not have a
continuum of time, and in those which do not separate words into two basic
classes of substantives and verbs the unconsciously possessed worldview of
native speakers of the language is radically different from that of the native
speakers of the Indo-European languages.
Thus it is now scientifically temerarious to hold that a universally
satisfying (rationalistic) analysis of the world must be made on the bases
which were available to the Greek philosophers. It would also appear that confusion would be rife if all the
worldviews of all the languages were to be included in an overall rationalistic
analysis. It is just possible, it
seems to me, that the meaning of KantÕs distinction between noumena and
phenomena is simply that we all observe the noumena, but we observe them as
partitioned into sets of phenomena by our languages and the thought processes
involved in using them. I propose
this on the basis of the linguistic work of Benjamin Whorf. See Language, Thought and Reality,
especially the chapter entitled ÒScience and Linguistics,Ó from which the
following is quoted:
When
linguists became able to examine critically and scientifically a large number
of languages of widely different patterns, their base of reference was
expanded; they experienced an interruption of phenomena hitherto held
universal, and a whole new order of significances came into their ken. It was found that the background
linguistic system (in other words, the grammar) of each language is not merely
a reproducing instrument for voicing ideas but rather is itself the shaper of
ideas, the program and guide for the individualÕs mental qctivity, for his analysis
of impressions, for his synthesis of his mental stock in trade. Formulation of ideas is not an
independent process, strictly rational in the old sense, but is part of a
particular grammar, and differs, from slightly to greatly, between different grammars. We dissect nature along lines laid down
by our native languages. The
categories and types that we isolate from the world of phenomena we do not find
there because they stare every observer in the face; on the contrary, the world
is presented in a kaleidoscopic flux of impressions which has to be organized
by our minds - and this means largely by the linguistic systems in our
minds. We cut nature up, organize
it into concepts, and ascribe significances as we do, largely because we are
parties to an agreement to organize it in this way - an agreemet that holds
throughout our speech community as is codified in the patterns of our
language. The agreement is, of
course, an implicit and unstated one, BUT ITS TERMS ARE ABSOLUTELY OBLIGATORY;
we cannot talk at all except by subscribing to the organization and
classification of data which the agreement decrees. (pp. 212-214)
"What
is truth?" is a concern of epistemology regarding all the forms of human
expression. There is scientific
truth, but there are also philosophical truth, artistic truth, and religious
truth. The term "truth"
itself is an abstract substantive used to describe a situation in which an
expression represents accurately, although not necessarily exhaustively, some
reality or some aspect of reality.
Truth always involves representation because it involves the use of a
medium, and tests for truth exist for each of the kinds of expression.
Many
reflections about truth are being omitted here, but one will be mentioned:
truth is a value. "Truth is
striven for in ordinary life, in fact-finding for business dealings, in social,
juridical, and political matters.
It is somethng people want to know. Likewise the sciences and philosophy want their conclusions
to be true." (Joseph Owens in Wood,
The Future of Metaphysics, p. 213) Nozick sees truth as a value which culminates a
process. We start, he explains,
from "belief," conviction that something is so, and by a process of
reference to correlatives and implications which he calls "tracking"
we validate this belief so that it becomes "true belief." (Philosophical
Explanations, chapter 3)
The
notion of value figures prominently in Ethics. Here we are using the word not as a technical philosophical
term, but as it is used in common parlance: a value is a thing or state to
esteem, to strive for, to view as a goal.
Although Nozick uses the notion of value liberally, he seems to keep
within the common understanding of it rather than to build a system around it.
The Limits of Human
Knowledge
It
would seem self-evident that human knowledge cannot predict its own limits,
i.e., on the basis of what is known we cannot know how much more there is to
know. Scientific knowledge, in
particular, can predict no limit to itself as long as it can make fresh
observations, because these lead to fresh reasoning. Historically there have been stages when scientists have
thought they knew all, but then they have found their neatly packaged system
torn apart by new discoveries.
Furthermore, this assumes that science is staying in its own territory;
there are things science does not know about but which are known to art or
religion or philosophy. Art and
religion, for their part, cannot know their own limits because they involve
imagination, that is, creativity, and by definition creativity does not know
its own limits.
Philosophy
shares with science one kind of limitlessness: it can build indefinitely on new
observations, but philosophy is in a position to judge that in some series of
thought new observations will not make a difference, and that, therefore, some
philosophical knowledge is definitive and some is definitively
inconclusive. The following is an
example of what is meant when one asserts that some philosophical knowledge is
definitively inconclusive:
Colin
McGinn has a new idea. In his book The Problem of Consciousness (1991)
he concluded that the difficulty of accounting for the presence of
consciousness in a world of physical objects and processes of the kind we
already understand is simply too great for human minds ever to overcome. Now in Problems in Philosophy,
he extends that verdict to philosophical issues involving other aspects of the
mind, such as the self, free will, meaning and knowledge. They, too, present real problems that
simply transcend our natural powers of understanding. That is something most of us will have felt personally from
time to time, but McGinn generalizes the inadequacy. It is the human intellect as such that cannot cope. (Review of Problems in Philosophy
by Barry Stroud in Times Literary Supplement, Feb. 25, 1994, N. 4743, p.
8. The reviewer does not think
that McGinn develops his thesis well.)
The
preceding reflection has another side: how much is there about our world that
we are missing? How much is
happening that our minds are unable to fathom? This is an epistemological question which has made sense
ever since Kant made us wonder what the noumena are. It would be exceedingly presumptuous of us at the present
stage of the development of human knowledge to suppose that the form of
perception and reflection we possess tells us all there is to know about
things. I think there is a virtual
certainty that there is more to the world than appears to our senses and the
instruments we use to aid them. To
think otherwise, i.e., that we understand all things, would put us back into
one or another form of the rationalism that philosophers have outgrown.
METAPHYSICS
The Nature of Metaphysics
As
stated above, ÒmetaphysicsÓ can be identified with ÒontologyÓ, but ontology, a
modern term, is properly restricted to the study of being as such or, which is
functionally the same, of the whole of reality, whereas metaphysics can
profitably be taken to refer to all speculative philosophy which does not
center on man's knowing (epistemology) or acting (ethics). It can be added that the terms
"general metaphysics" and "ontology" are taken as
synonymous by some philosophers.
(Copleston, A History of Philosophy, Vol. 3, p. 356)
A
well used notion of metaphysics is Òthe study of the kinds of things there are
and their modes of being.Ó (Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, article on history of metaphysics) We can, however, find generally acceptable descriptions of
metaphysics which present more detail, such as "The aim of metaphysics is
a comprehensive conceptual scheme in the light of which the whole of experience
can be organized and become intelligible.
It is for this reason sometimes said (for example, by Whitehead) to be
concerned with the most general and pervasive features of the world, and at
others (for example, by Plato) to be the most synoptic of the
sciences." (Errol E. Harris
in Robert P. Wood, Ed., The Future of Metaphysics, p. 200)
To
pursue Whitehead's explanation, "... in a much-quoted passage, Whitehead
stated that 'Speculative philosophy is the endeavor to frame a coherent
logical, necessary system of general ideas in terms of which every element of
our experience can be interpreted.'
The system is to be 'coherent' in the sense that 'no entity can be
conceived in complete abstraction from the system of the universe.... The term
'logical' has its ordinary meaning, including ... consistency, or lack of
contradiction, the definition of constructs in logical terms, the
exemplification of general logical notions in specific instances, and the
principles of inference.'
Whitehead goes on to state, however, that 'Philosophers can never hope
finally to formulate ... metaphysical first principles. Weakness of insight and deficiencies of
language stand in the way inexorably.
Words and phrases must be stretched towards a generalization foreign to
their ordinary usages; and however such elements of language be stabilized as
technicalities, they remain metaphors mutely appealing for an imaginative
leap.'" (R. M. Martin in
Wood, The Future of Metaphysics, pp. 186-7. Refers to Whitehead's Process
and Reality, pp. 4-6)
An
important notion of metaphysics which includes, however, elements which are not
of common agreement is that of Kant.
"... Kant used the term 'metaphysics' to refer to all a priori
speculation on questions that cannot be answered by scientific observation and
experiment. As he formulates it:
metaphysics 'is the system of pure reason, that is, the science which exhibits
in systematic connection the whole body (true as well as illusory) of
philosophical knowledge arising out of pure reason.' Taken in a broader sense (so as to include the critique of
reason), metaphysics comprehends 'the investigations of all that can ever be
known a priori as well as the exposition of that which constitutes a system of
the pure philosophical modes of knowledge of this type ....' Metaphysics is either metaphysics of
nature or metaphysics of morals.
'The former contains all the principles of pure reason that are derived
from mere concepts ... and employed in the theoretical knowledge of all
things; the latter, the principles which in a priori fashion determine and make
necessary all our actions.'
(Joseph J. Kockelmans in Wood, The Future of Metaphysics, p. 231;
reference to Kant: Critique of Pure Reason, transl. by Norman Kemp
Smith, New York, 1965, pp. 21-33 {esp. 30-31})
Kant's
definition is objectionable for two reasons. One is his notion of the metaphysics of morals, which is
clever and powerful, but which fails to convince the many, many thinkers who
are against or at least suspicious of a universal deontology (a topic of
Ethics). The other objection to
Kant's definition is its rationalism.
His postulate of a power of pure reason which operates independently of
the observations which come to it can scarcely be taken seriously any more,
although the broader application of what Kant saw, that our mind imposes shapes
and forms on the reality it perceives has become part of the patrimony of human
wisdom.
In
spite of criticism of Kant as a metaphysician, all commentators hold that he
stands among the ranks of the all time greats of metaphysics. Some pre-kantian metaphysicians are
Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics, Plotinus, Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, and
Leibnitz. While Kant changed
metaphysics, he did not kill it, and some post-kantian metaphysicians are
Schopenhauer, Hegel, Bergson, and Whitehead.
Although
modern Western philosophy generally shuns metaphysics by name, numerous modern
philosophers are closer to metaphysics than might appear at first sight. Phenomenologists and existentialists,
by describing the world in a way free of suppositions of duality between mind
and body and between subject and object, come up with a structure of reality
that fits the common definition of metaphysical description. Thus, to our list of metaphysicians we
shall add the modern phenomenologists Edmund Husserl, Nicolai Hartmann and
Maurice Merleau-Ponty as well as the existentialists Martin Heidegger,
Jean-Paul Sartre, and Gabriel Marcel
It
is even possible to see something of the metaphysician in as non-metaphysical,
no-hocus-pocus and no-hidden-entities American philosopher as John Dewey. Copleston remarks, "Obviously,
Dewey's philosophy is not a metaphysics if by this term we mean a study or
doctrine of meta-empirical reality.
But though, as has already been noted, he denies, in one place at least,
that any general theory of reality is needed or even possible, it is clear
enough that he develops a world-view.
And world-views are generally classed under the heading of
metaphysics. It would be ingenuous
to say that Dewey simply takes the world as he finds it. For the plain fact is that he
interprets it. For the matter of
that, in spite of all that he has to say against general theories, he does not
really prohibit all attempts to determine the generic traits, as he puts it, of
existence of all kinds." (A
History of Philosophy, vol VIII, p. 376)
Questions of ontology
In
explaining the term philosophy I mentioned several metaphysical questions. Now we shall examine some of these.
Is there anything that can
be said about everything
other than that it has being
(exists in some way)?
It
is possible to isolate the notion of being and scrutinize it, prescinding from
closely related notions like unity and multiplicity, permanence and flux. To do this requires extreme effort to
avoid aspects of being such as these, and it practically involves ignoring the
whole of Western philosophy since Plato.
A
modern effort to do just this has been that of Martin Heidegger and his method
of investigating Being as such.
Heidegger himself was not at all concerned to forge links between
fundamental ontology and less general areas of ontology. His method, however, seems to furnish
clues to this. While Heidegger
expresses his thought preeminently in Being and Time, he explains his
philosophical project in much more intelligible terms in a later slim volume
entitled On Time and Being.
If,
beyond the notion of being itself, with or without a heideggerian analysis,
there are statements that can be made about anything and everything, if there
are completely universal predicates, they can be called transcendental
attributes of being, or, simply, "transcendentals." Highly developed by the Scholastics of
the Middle Ages, the notion of transcendentals is generally disregarded in our
time because it is not usually dissociated from aspects of Scholastic
philosophy which have been discredited (principally, its mistaking of
descriptions of the world for analyses of it), but its simplicity and universal
applicability can be appreciated without the Scholastic baggage. This is not the same as the Platonic
transcendentals, the Forms of the Good, the True, etc. which are supposed to
exist outside changeable beings.
In the following section we will see how there are two transcendentals,
unity and relation.
How are unity and
multiplicity related?
It
seems that everything is somehow one and somehow multiple. Wherever we direct our attention there
are wholes and parts, there are unities and diversities, and everywhere unity
exists in multiplicity. Diverse
elements seek to unify themselves, and unities tend to dissolve into their
parts. Furthermore, we are aware
of no part which is not a unity in itself, and we are aware of no unity which
has no parts. The urge to ponder
these observations and to explain them has been one of the sources of
philosophy in the West as it has been a source of philosophy and of religion in
the East
The
question about the relationship between Òthe one and the manyÓ was asked by the
Pre-Socratics, and it is still being asked in Western philosophy because no one
has yet found a totally satisfactory answer to it. It is also the central question in Indian philosophy. One might go so far as to hold with
Iris Murdoch that ontology (which she calls metaphysics) is the
intellectual activity of accounting for perceived unities when other ways of
accounting for them - common sense, science, art, and religion - are judged to
be inadequate. (See page 1 of
Murdoch, Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals.) In a similar vein, Nozick holds that there are two principal
(and perhaps only) topics in ontology (which he also calls metaphysics): what
is unity? which he calls "The Identity of the Self," and he is
concerned with human self-identity, and what is being? which he calls "Why
is There Something Rather than Nothing?" (Philosophical Explanations, chapters 1 {self} and 2
{being}.)
Much
of what can be said about unity in multiplicity derives from Aristotle, who was
interested in unified things and how they became such. According to Aristotle, "Among
authentic modes of unity we find first mere being-together, whether, to cite an
example often repeated later, we are dealing with a mere heap, or with unities
which arise from binding, glueing, or nailing things together, as for example a
bundle. Next, Aristotle considers
those unities which consist in a mere coherence of material, such as the unity
of a plank. Then follows the unity
resting on form, such as the unity of a marble ball. The unity of a living
being represents the last in this series.... All these are forms of unity for individuals. To them must
be added an entirely new mode of unity, that of the general, the unity of
logos, as Aristotle rather cautiously expresses it. This is primarily a matter of the unity which is expressed
in a concept, for example the unity of the human race as the unity of the
concept 'man'?" ." (Martin,
General Metaphysics, p. 109.)
Another
of Aristotle's ways of looking at unity was to consider that things, objects,
have an underlying unity as "substances," and that the changeable
aspects of substances are "accidents." Expressed in terms of naive understanding, this
relationship is unassailable, but expressed philosophically it has been taken
to assert that there is some mysterious being lurking within real beings and
that the realities we sense about real beings supposedly belong to the mysterious
substrate. Modern minds, starting
most notably with John Locke, reject the notion of substance as thus
presented. While this does not
seem to the writer to be fair to Aristotle, it raises the problem of
description versus definition alluded to above. In other words, substance-accident seems to be a mere
description rather than an insight into being.
More
immediately useful is the division of unities into three kinds: A.
PHYSICO-CHEMICAL unity, the object of science. B. SYNERGISTIC unity, which has a scientific aspect, but
also has a specific intelligible content in that synergistic entities, things
which work together, are not one between themselves, but are as one to others
which are outside of them. C.
INTENTIONAL unity, which is not in itself a unity of physical forces, but is
the unity of entities perceiving one another or taking a positive stance toward
one another. It is debatable
whether or not intentionality can be predicated of all beings, but it certainly
can be predicated of all living beings, and it is a prime element of human
existence. In humans it is spread
throughout a double continuum of perception and affection, of knowledge and
love. This enumeration of the
kinds of unity does not separate the processes of unity from their products; it
is not of statically conceived beings concerning which the question of becoming
is to be asked; it points to unity itself. Intentionality is taken here in the sense introduced
by Franz Brentano.
An
observation that applies to the three kinds of unity is that the whole is
different from the sum of its parts. Everywhere, from the atom-subatomic
particle relatioship to the galaxy-star relationship, from the word-letter
relationship to the discourse-word relationship, the whole looks different and
acts differently from its constituents.
This is not to say that a whole cannot be explained by a complete
synthesis of its parts; it means that the parts have taken on, so to speak, a
new life in connection with one another.
As Nozick puts it, "The theory of value, formulated below, will
give sense to the notion that a whole not only is different from the sum of its
parts, but is greater than that sum -- greater in intrinsic value." (Philosophical
Explanations, p. 104.)
The
modern notion of systems, expanded from science into philosophy,
provides a general framework for describing and dealing with all kinds of
unities and for the wholes which are not simply sums of parts. Following Ervin Laszlo, we can state a
theory of natural systems which does exactly this: "THEORY: R = f{a,b,c,d), where
a,b,c,d are independent variables having the joint function R ('natural
system'). a: coactive relation of
parts resulting in ordered wholeness in the state of the system ('systemic state property'); b: function of adaptation to
environmental disturbances resulting in the re-establishment of a previous steady state in the
system ('system-cybernetics I');
c: function of adaptation to enviromental disturbances resulting in the
reorganization of the system's state, involving, with a high degree of
probability, an overall gain in the system's negentropy and information
content ('system-cybernetics II')';
d: dual functional-structural adaptation: with respect to
subsystems (adaptation as a systemic whole) and suprasystems (adaptation
as coacting part) ('holon property'). (Ervin Laszlo, Introduction to Systems Philosophy,
pp. 35-36.)
Laszlo
goes on to explain cognitive systems, which are otherwise called
operations of mind or intentional (as defined above) actions. The same general formula applies to
them as to natural systems. (Introduction
to Systems Philosophy, pp. 124-138.)
Laszlo
sees these two types of systems, which are seemingly irreducible the one to the
other, as facets of the same reality.
He asserts,
We
note that the theories applying to natural and to cognitive systems are
isomorphic, with the consequence that when switching from the one to the other
system, wo do not necessitate changes in theory. The content or referent of the theory changes;
its form remains invariant.
We obtain a parallel series of independent variables applying to both
varieties of systems. This
provides our ontology with a fundamental concept: that of the natural-cognitive
(i.e., psychophysical) system.
Such systems are not 'dual' but 'biperspectival': they are single,
self-consistent systems of events, observable from two points of view. When
'lived,' such a system is a system of mind-events, viz., a 'cognitive
system.' When looked at from any
other viewpoint, the system is a system of physical-events, i.e., a 'natural
system.' The physical and mental
sets of events in the systems are correlates; the systems within which they are
found, or which they constitute, are identical. Here identity is predicated on the ground of the invariance
of the two theories: if systems of events, however different the latter may be
in themselves, are isomorphically structured, so that their respective theories
do not change form when passing from the one to the other, then these systems
are identical qua systems.
There are no grounds on which we could differentiate between them....
The
psychophysical thesis of this framework for an ontology can be stated as
follows. Sets of irreducibly
different mental and physical events constitute an identical psychophysical
system, disclosed through the invariance of the respective theories. The basic entities of systems
philosophy are non-dualistic psychophysical systems, termed 'biperspectival
natural-cognitive systems. (Introduction to Systems Philosophy, pp.
153-154.)
In
conclusion,"unity" is a transcendental because something does not
exist unless it has some kind of internal coherence, a oneness that sets it
apart from anything else, and some kind of permanence that stands up to change. All the same, "relation" is
also a transcendental if we accept our initial observation that unity and
multiplicity are everywhere. It is
easy for the modern, scientific mind to accept relation as a transcendental. Philosophers, however, who posit the
existence of an absolute God can admit that relation is a transcendental only
by considering being as an equivocal term, according to which the being of God
is basically dissimilar to the being of the world. In this case the relation of God to the world is basically
dissimilar to all other relations.
How are change and
permanence related?
We
have looked at the question of the one and the many as though it dealt with
static beings, as though we could, as it were, take a photograph of all beings
and investigate their relationships in the photograph. We can do this because our Western
minds tend to look at the world this way and in so doing they separate from
this view of things the aspect of change.
That we do this is shown by the structure of language. Not all language families separate
nouns and verbs as decisively as Indo-European languages do, but at least all
the languages which have served as matrices for philosophy speak in some way of
action and of actors.
Mentally
restoring change to the photograph produces a motion picture in which some
things or aspects of things which are seen in the photo taken in moment A are
still there in moment B. We have
skirted the epistemological question of the validity of our perception of
duration in things by pointing to the observer, who is aware of some
self-identity in moments A and B.
Self-identity or any identity maintained through change is clearly a
kind of oneness, a unity in the midst of diversity which allows for successive,
varied relationships
To What End, if any, Does the
World Exist?
The
most basic thing that can be said about this question, indeed, according to
many, the only thing that can be said about it is that it is highly
speculative. It is so highly
metaphysical that even to say that the question cannot be answered is a
metaphysical statement. In other
words, the question does make sense, and we are drawn to ask it, and the way we
answer it or fail to answer it tells something about our worldview, about who
we are and about our limitations.
The
question of the end or purpose of the world, i. e., why the world exists has
tended historically to be answered by religion rather than by philosophy. In the major Western religions it is
totally linked to the notion of God and it derives its answer from the knowledge
religious people judge that they have about God's intentions. Some systems of philosophy are similar
to this, but others are not.
Philosophy can, for instance, talk about ultimate causes and purposes
without bringing into play a divine mind which conceives of them.
What are good and evil?
In
considering this as a metaphysical question we refer to the transcultural human
experience that things go right or wrong on small scales and on large scales,
and to the legends and archtypes of societies far separated in time and
place. There are states of affairs
which are desirable, approvable, felicitous, and there are states of affairs
which are the opposite. Indeed, there is here a question of opposites, contraries,
and fatal contradictories which runs through history, art, and metaphysics. We
say that a thing is good or bad and we say that an action is good or bad. We say that people and their actions
are good or bad, and we also use these terms to refer to non-human events and
states. Good/bad, goodness/evil
are in wide-spread human use as normative concepts which suppose a standard.
Metaphysics
cannot stay clear of the good-evil relationship. If a philosopher tried to construct a world view in which
there were no good or evil, the interpreters of this world view would say that
it is a good world or a bad world whether its inventor liked them to make this
judgment or not.
Fortunately
for students of metaphysics there is a limited array of possible meanings of
good and evil in metaphysical systems.
Thus,
1)
good is an ideal of perfection that the world and its parts strive to attain
(the Platonic view),
2)
good is what can be said about one thing that draws other things to it (the
Aristotelian view),
3)
being as being is good, and evil is a lack of being (the Scholastic view),
4)
good is a force that moves things to act appropriately (a common theistic view,
although also Bergsonian).
(The
fourth of these analyses allows for the possibility of its converse, which is
the Manichean view, that evil is a force which moves things to act
inappropriately. We shall leave aside the Manichean view because it is a
useless hypothesis which is not needed for explaining the tension between good
and evil. Certainly, the Manichean
view accentuates the consideration of evil, but even among non-Manicheans the
topic of good is more often than not paired with that of evil in what is called
the problem of evil: how does it happen that evil infects an otherwise good
world? Often this problem is seen
in a theistic context (why does a good God allow evil?), but in Western
philosophies such as that of Schopenhauer, and certainly in Indian philosophies
the problem of evil is treated without reference to a good God. For an example of the frequency of
treatment of the problem of good and evil as opposed to the study of good I
note the (1996) online library catalog of a large, secular American university,
in which it is fruitless to search for "good", but 91 lines respond
to the search command "good and evil".)
The
four analyses of good do not contradict one another, and they can be understood
as four aspects of one general notion of good, which is that things are good in
so far as they are unified, in so far as they are one. Thus a force can move
others because it is unified in itself, a being can be sought by others because
it has definite lineaments, and beings strive for their own perfection, a state
which to them or to observers of them looks satisfying and fulfilling for them. This is a view of good that has been
maturing for many years in my mind.
In opposition to it one can assert that it is merely a tautology, that,
thus understood, the term ÒgoodÓ has no content other than that of unity or
oneness, and maybe this is so in some disembodied, intellectual scheme of
things, but we humans use the term in ways which are different from the ways in
which we use the term Òone,Ó and this constitutes a distinct or special
meaning, i.e., there is discourse about ÒgoodÕ as well as discourse about Òone.Ó
Aside
from the Manichean view of evil the array of opinions about it is limited. Starting from the notion that evil is
the opposite, contrary, or contradictory of good, the possibilities are that it
is a lack of good, that it is a lack of good where the lack is not appropriate,
or that it is repulsive. We will
exclude the first of these because it is not in accordance with normal usage of
the terms to say that evil is directly the absence of good. In other words, in normal usage of the
terms we do not say that evil is the contradictory of good, that wherever good
is not found, evil is.
Looking
now at good as unity, unifiedness, we can see that several things can go wrong
with it. The process of
unification can be disrupted, the proper unity of an existing thing or act can
be disrupted, an act can be directed at a goal that will be disruptive to the
actor, or the unity of one entity (thing or act) precludes that of another
The
first three of the things that can go wrong has to do with the united being
considered by itself: it impairs or destroys its perfection. Evil is a disruption of the process or
the product of unification. It is
also misdirection of action: one could describe it as action directed toward an
entity which objectively speaking is repulsive to the actor, an entity that
will impair or destroy the actor's unity.
Perfection is a useful descriptive term here as long as we take
it in the sense of relative perfection, the degree of perfection suitable for
the normal existence of the entity, and not in the sense of an unattainable
absolute perfection
The
precluding of the good of one entity by that of another, the conflict between
actions or things which would in themselves be good but are mutually exclusive,
which cannot exist together, is a kind of evil which is hard to understand and
deal with. One entity is being
harmed by another, one suffers at the expense of another, and this is a dilemma
at least to the extent that the greatest good to be achieved will not be the sum
of the greatest good of the parties involved. This last dynamic of good and evil, applied to the
observable world on a large scale, has been expressed by Whitehead: "The
ultimate evil in the temporal world is deeper than any specific evil. It lies in the fact that the past
fades, that time is a 'perpetual perishing.' Objectification involves elimination. The present fact has not the past fact
with it in any full immediacy. The
process of time veils the past below distinctive feeling. There is a unison of becoming among
things in the present. Why should
there not be novelty without loss of this direct unison of immediacy among
things? In the temporal world, it
is the empirical fact that process entails loss: the past is present under an
abstraction. But there is no
reason, of any ultimate metaphysical generality, why this should be the whole
story. The nature of evil is that
the characters of things are mutually obstructive. Thus the depths of life require a process of selection. But the selection is elimination as the
first step towards another temporal order seeking to minimize obstructive
modes. Selection is at once the
measure of evil, and the process of its evasion. It means the discarding the element of obstructiveness in
fact. No element in fact is
ineffectual: thus the struggle with evil is a process of building up a mode of
utilization by the provision of intermediate elements introducing a complex
structure of harmony."
(Process and Reality, p. 517.)
What are the most general
categories of being?
Following
Aristotle, the analysis of being into such categories as substance, accident,
quality, and quantity was a standard part of Western philosophy until and
including Kant. This analysis is
no longer fashionable, and even if a metaphysically inclined philosopher were
to engage in it, it would add little to our understanding of the world. Another division of being is into
material and spiritual. Many
philosophers have held that there is a spiritual world within or in addition to
the material world which we see and touch. Modern, non-Christian Western philosophers tend to deny that
there is such a division. The main
philosophical source of Western thinking about the spiritual world is, of
course, Plato, but the modern notion of the dichotomy of matter and spirit, of
an abyss between the two, is traced to Descartes.
Is there a supreme being?
Often
this is phrased as the question of the existence of God: do we reason to the
existence of God or do we have experience of God or neither or both? This is in theory a philosophical
question, and the treatment of it is called natural theology (also, theodicy),
but the major interest in it is theological, religious. Thus under Ethics we shall note
implications of the position that God exists, but we shall not dwell on
them. As a matter of fact, many
conceptions of God - as being perfect good, as being an ideal of good, as being
the cause of all good, as being that to which all things tend - lead to ethics
systems which are scarcely different from non-religious ones. Perhaps the theistic concept which most
varies from the philosophical one is that of God as a lawgiver who can
arbitrarily decree that some actions are good and some are bad.
Philosophy of People and
Society
Turning
to metaphysical questions which have to do with people and society, we have
first:
What is man? how does man
fit into the universe?
Perhaps
the most perplexing of all philosophical questions concerns the philosopher and
the philosopher's fellow humans.
The ancient perception of human littleness has, to say the least, not
been displaced by scientific knowledge of the vastness of the universe. Nevertheless, the ancient perception of
the specialness of humans, who are able to search the heavens and look into the
past and the future, has been accentuated by the discovery of more and more
tools which help them do this. We
have been and are paradoxes to ourselves.
I propose that two principal schools of thought challenge his assertion:
scientific reductionism, which holds that the human whole is no greater than
the sum of its parts, and that theism which explains everything about us by
holding that God made it that way.
Poets and philosophers, on the contrary, are moved by the strange and
seemingly unique human condition.
It
seems to me that the place of humans in the world is best seen philosophically
by considering three salient kinds of unity found in the human person. Or, rather, the human person has a
three-fold kind of unified being: organic, intentional, and social. Organic unity is shared at least
with other local life forms and is an exceedingly complex interrelated
structure and synergy which is located in time and space. Intentional unity is the outcome of an action which
connects us as conscious beings with objects and events whether or not they are
locally connected with us.
Intentional unity can be either intellective or emotional or both. Social unity can be looked at as an extension of individual organic
unity, but it is rendered even more complex by the spectrum of intentional
unities which reside in it. Social unity refers to any human collectivity, from
couples to families to groups to nations to the whole of humankind.
What
does it mean to be a good human being?
Metaphysically, if a certain degree of organic, intentional, and social
unity are found in a person, that person satisfies the conditions for
goodness. What this Òcertain
degreeÓ might be and what purpose it serves to call someone ÒgoodÓ principally
because he or she is an ideal physical specimen or is a civic minded citizen
are questions that a philosopher of good may want to consider. Certain activities of people, however,
lie within the field of ethics, and it is in connection with them that we
customarily speak of good people and their good actions. We can mention here, however, that on
the one hand the social unity of humans makes us terribly interdependent, but
that on the other hand it enormously increases our ability to act: it multiples
our synergistic power. We see that
the synergistic union involved in this is a greater good than chaotic human
action, and we are involved in synergistic action in society whether we like it
or not. Thus we can assert that
society is good, but in such a way that the individual as such is also
good. It seems to me that only
narrowly focused extremists who hold either that society is more real than the
individual or that the individual is more real than society would overlook this
simple relationship.
The
peculiar richness of the human person as experienced by people themselves and
as compared with non-human beings leads to investigation and speculation into
what it is about humans that is different from the rest. Human consciousness surely sets us
apart from animals whether or not there is a continuum of degrees of
consciousness culminating in humans.
An enormous amount of scientific and philosophical effort has been
expended in studying consciousness without, it seems to me, much success, and
yet it seems impossible to dispense with the notion of consciousness. It comes up, for instance, in ethics
because situations are ethical only if there is a consciousness of self present
in them.
Some
philosophers and many religious people have held that human consciousness is a
function of an immaterial soul. In
the hypothesis that they exist, immaterial human souls could scarcely be the
sole occupants of a spiritual world, and all explanations of them include
reference to at least one totally non-material being, God, and some
explanations of them involve additional spiritual beings such as angels. An extensive philosophical treatment of
a supposed spiritual world would derive logically from the general categories
of being.
What is the destiny of man?
"What
happens to us upon death?" is a question of both metaphysics and religion,
and to some extent of art.
Metaphysical treatment of the matter has traditionally in the West been
a function of the interplay of the dichotomous notions of matter and spirit,
material and immaterial. Needless
to say, many philosophers, including those who explicitly reject religion, have
supported this dichotomy, and have thus been able to hold that the human spirit
or soul continues to exist in spite of the death of the body. One wonders, however, how much the generality
of post-classical Western philosophers would have dwelt on this if they had not
had a Christian background.
It
is not necessary to suppose that there is in human persons a body-soul,
material-spiritual fusion in order to hold that death is not their final
destiny. If humans act in a way
which transcends time and space this may be ascribed to a type of being which
possesses a correlative transcendance.
Of course human intentionality, mentioned above, does this, and on this
basis there may be something about humans which exists outside time and space
and which, therefore, is not affected by death. This does not imply that the
human person lives on after death chronologically. Our naive notion of time needs much
correction by both science and philosophy. Indeed, this view probably could not have arisen until
modern scientific knowledge showed that time and space are quite different from
what earlier science had supposed them to be. Thus such dissimilar moderns as Merleau-Ponty, the
phenomenologist, and Alfred North Whitehead, the philosopher of science and
mathematics, have contributed to an understanding of this human
transcendence. Combining this
reflection with my previous observation that there is more to the world than
appears to our senses, I concludes to the overwhelming rational probability
that there is something about us which is not terminated by death.
What is human freedom?
The
most general and widespread notion of human freedom, that we have the power to
choose between actions, has to be qualified, and more specific notions of it
are controversial. Still, the
notion that we have some conscious control of our actions, some ability to
determine that we will do this and not do that is too much a part of the human
experience to dismiss out of hand.
To say that we are never free in our actions is to say that freedom is a
total illusion, and this can be maintained for either philosophical or
scientific reasons. Scientific
reductionism does away with freedom, but at the peril of undermining its own
scientific method, which is to be open to the as yet unknown data that call for
new explanations. Negation of
freedom for philosophical, not scientific reasons, appears rather rarely in
Western philosophy: Spinoza and
the Stoics can be cited as examples, but there are no disciples of Spinoza and
the Stoics among us, and their doctrine about freedom is too intimately
connected to the rest of their philosophy to be considered apart from it.
By
human freedom we do not mean "freedom of will", a notion that implies
the existence in the human person of a faculty or power of will. We are not arguing against freedom of
the will, but we are asserting that to speak in these terms implies a
philosophical psychology which has been outgrown and which is not needed for
understanding human freedom. We
could also point out that "will" is a loaded term that explains
little while itself requiring a great deal of explanation.
It
is generally conceded that the feeling which humans have of freedom, of not
being coerced to do this action or of not being coerced to do this action
instead of that one does not constitute proof of freedom. By now we are too aware of hidden
forces and hidden motivation to be comfortable with such a line of
argumentation.
Among
philosophical reasons given for human freedom, the one proposed by Thomas
Aquinas is perhaps the simplest and most direct for those who adhere to an
metaphysics of good, as we do in this essay (where we say that to be unified is
to be good). That is to say that
if we act for the sake of the good, only pure good (which to Thomas is God) is
totally irresistible; other goods, being limited, can have only limited
influence over us and therefore not compel us to seek them. In all cases, however, the good
attracts us only to the extent that we know it. Serious objections to this line of
reasoning are raised by the phenomenologist Paul Ricoeur, who - quite aside
from his phenomenological method, which presents itself as being opposed to
ontology on principle - points out that the Thomistic position includes the
contradiction that we are self-determined only if something else determines
us. To Ricoeur himself, however,
this relation between self-determination and determination by others is not a
contradiction, but a paradox, a paradox which is studied by his
phenomenological method. (Freedom
and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary is a rich phenomenological
study of human freedom detached from ontology. RicoeurÕs treatment of the Thomistic argument is in the section
entitled "Possibility of a Definition of Freedom in the Margins of
Cosmology" on pages 190 to 197.)
Whatever
we think of Aquinas and Ricoeur, we can point to a simple notion of freedom,
one that is sufficient for the purpose of the present essay, and to the reason
for it in the observation that freedom is an attribute of some human actions
because the mind sees more than one course of action and sees that no one of
them is compelling: we must choose in default of other persons or factors
choosing for us. To put it
concretely, Buridan's ass might die of starvation, but people, when placed in
the same situation, will not.
Going
more deeply than this notion of freedom, we can point to the distillation of
philosophical conceptions of human freedom which Mortimer Adler and his
associates presented in The Idea of Freedom. Elaborated and discussed over the course of 1200 pages,
human freedom generically conceived is described thus: "a man is free who
has in himself the ability or power to make what he does his own action and
what he achieves his own property." (vol. I, p. 614 and vol II, p.
16.) In all conceptions of freedom
there is a self and an "other," (which may be within the same acting
person as the self) and a power in the self which is not under the domination
of the "other." (vol. I, pp. 608-616). This common notion is analogously found in five kinds of
freedom which Adler finds in the philosophers (vol. II, pp. 5-11):
1. Circumstantial
freedom of self-realization, "a freedom which is possessed by any
individual who, under favorable circumstances, is able to act as he wishes for
his own good as he sees it."
2. Acquired
freedom of self-perfection, "a freedom which is possessed only by those
men who, through acquired virtue or wisdom, are able to will or live as they
ought in conformity to the moral law or an ideal befitting human nature."
3. Natural
freedom of self-determination, "a freedom which is possessed by all men,
in virtue of a power inherent in human nature, whereby a man is able to change
his own character by deciding for himself what he shall do or shall
become."
4. Political
liberty, "a freedom which is possessed only by citizens who, through the
right of suffrage and the right of juridical appeal against the abuses of
government, are able to participate in making the positive law under which they
live and to alter the political institutions of their society."
5. Collective
freedom, "a freedom which will be possessed by humanity or the human race
in the future when, through the social use of the knowledge of both natural and
social necesssities, men achieve the ideal mode of association that is the goal
of mankind's development and are able to direct their communal life in
accordance with such necessities."
Nozick
points out that many philosophers treat human freedom (which he terms
"freedom of the will") in connection with punishment/sanction
because, they say, we do not deserve punishment unless we are free. (Philosophical Explanations, p.
291.) Nozick himself, however,
thinks of freedom in terms of value: to the extent that our actions are our
own, are not forced on us, they have value. Nozick asks, what are the conditions of our actions' being
valuable? (Philosophical
Explanations, chapter 4.)
PHILOSOPHICAL
ELEMENTS IN GENERAL ETHICS
Preface
As
I stated in the chapter on philosophy in general, ethics concerns itself with
the appropriateness of human actions.
Like all definitions of ethics or general statements about it, this
notion of ethics is loaded with assumptions and hidden meanings, and is
intended only to evoke in the reader's mind a vague recognition of the subject
without reference to the assumptions and hidden meanings.
Although
it is not true that all philosophers are ethicists - philosophers of ethics -
the great names in the history of philosophy, metaphysicians or
anti-metaphysicians as they may have been, have, on the whole, been
ethicists. A roster of notable
ethicists includes Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics, Augustine, Aquinas, Hobbes,
Hume, Kant, Schopenhauer, Mill, Nietzsche, Dewey, Sartre, Moore, Rawls, and
Habermas.
To
proceed beyond the introductory notion of ethics, we observe that human beings
sometimes or often act as wholes.
This assertion does not describe life sustaining activities such as
digestion, and it does not describe biological reflexes, although either can
involve virtually all of the body.
The actions under discussion are those of the whole person: the
observable body and the subjectively experienced consciousness, which, taken
together, we shall term the self.
In asserting this we are trying to avoid subtleties of phenomenology and
other particular philosophical schools, but we are trying to do justice to
common human experience.
Of
the actions which involve the whole of the human person we can at least say
that they take place at a higher level of organization than the generality of
observable physical actions. They
include perceptions of objects or situations that are distant or future; they
include orientation toward abstractions; they include that ability to act in
the absence of external determinants which we have called human freedom. Their guiding principles have to be of
a corresponding order of complexity, abstraction, and freedom. Thus, as observable physical actions
take place in an environment of physical determinants and correspond to the
same, ethical actions take place
in an environment of, and correspond to, factors of complexity, abstraction,
and freedom. These factors are
qualitatively different from physical determination, but they are not of a
mysterious world alien to the world of fact. Rather, they represent a sector of that world of fact, a
sector in which actions do not "have to" happen, but
"should" happen. In
short, the rules of human conduct, ethical rules, are to actions of the whole
human person as physical laws are to physical actions, and ethical rules are
both like and unlike physical laws, just as human action is like and unlike
other physical action. The
implications of this for the formal study of ethics is that the disjunction
between "is" and "ought" is a false and misleading one.
Concern
about the disjunction between "is" and "ought" was brought
into English language philosophy by David Hume 250 years ago, when he pointed
out that philosophers were not showing how one could reason from the
"is," the state of affairs, to the "ought," or what should
be done about it. There have been
many English speaking ethicists since Hume, and this disjunction and a
frustrating lack of success in overcoming it have remained at the heart of
their ethics until the present time.
Currently, however, there is a tendency to discredit the importance of
the disjunction as philosophers look to other frameworks for studying the
question of ethical obligation
There
are expectations about the actions of humans as whole selves; in given
circumstances people are expected to act in certain ways, to do certain
things. The expectations are by no
means uniform across cultures or even from one person to another, and even when
the expectations are the same the reasons given for them often vary from one
observer to another. Nevertheless,
there are some observable commonalities among the expectations. Saving the consideration of these empirical
expectation for a treatment of descriptive ethics, we now proceed to examine the question
of what we might expect of human actions in view of what we know humans to be,
i.e., in view of a philosophical description of humans. My basis here is what I have asserted
about the philosophy of people and society under metaphysics.
Before
investigating principles of ethics either descriptively or deductively one
needs to clarify the relationships between several closely related
concepts. First, the difference
between ethics and morals.
Although these terms are sometimes used interchangeably, moral is
generally used to describe the person rather than the person's actions. A moral person is commonly said to be a
good person. Ethical, on
the other hand, is generally used as an attribute of actions. Thus a moral person performs ethical
actions, and generally the actions of moral persons are ethical, although the
basic morality of a person is not necessarily compromised by the performance of
some unethical actions, i.e., not every action of a moral person need be
ethical. Here we are concerned
with people's actions, with ethics.
Still, under the heading of virtues we shall see that ethical
action can be defined in relationship to attributes of the moral person. I propose this distinction between the
terms ethics and morals as one of common usage in English and in
European languages in general.
Even if other words were employed, however, the difference would remain
between words which describe conduct and ones which describe status.
Close
in concept to the above distinction between ethics and morals is one of usage
relating to practical fields.
Thus, people commonly speak of medical ethics or business ethics rather
than medical morals or business morals.
To some extent this is due to a deliberate intent to separate the
judgment of conduct in these areas from judgment about individuals. It is more acceptable to have public
debate about our ethics than it is about our morals. This common usage reinforces the terminology which arises
from the fundamental distinction mentioned above. This is very clear in American usage regarding medical and
business ethics, and it holds also in international communications in the same
fields.
Secondly
there are three similar sets of attributes concerning the expectations of human
actions: customary, legal, and ethical.
Customs are ways of doing things which a society approves of and which
are enforced by societal pressure.
Laws are also ways of doing things acknowledged by a society, but in
their case the society enforces the observance with administratively imposed
sanctions, principally negative sanctions for transgressions. Ethical expectations, ethical rules,
are thought to derive their force from outside the individual (whether from
society, from universal human nature, or from God) and to be sanctioned by the
source of their force. The
boundaries between these three sets of expectations are not always clear, and
some people identify legal and ethical expectations, but there are generally
recognized differences between them, especially that ethical expectations are
related to moral status, that is, to the basic goodness or badness of the
individual.
Norms
What
is a good human action? What is a
bad one? Why are some human
actions good and some bad? What is
it about a human action that makes it good or bad? What does it mean when we say that a human action is good or
bad? What measuring stick do we
use to determine if a given action is good or bad? Each of these questions is a way of putting the central
issue of ethics, which is that of knowing the norms or standards of good or bad
human action, the norms or standards of right and wrong.
We
could at this point immediately consider one by one the more notable ethical
norms which philosophers have proposed.
To make this useful we would conclude with some judgment about which
norms are better or best and why this is so. Reasonable as this procedure would be, I wish to proceed
from the more to the less general.
We shall therefore first cross the bridge from philosophy of people and
society to ethics by asking, how could a human action be good or bad?
I
asserted under metaphysics that "things are good in so far as they are
unified, in so far as they are one."
If we understand actions to be transitions between one state and another
or, conversely, we understand things to be states between one action and
another, then it follows that goodness can be said of actions which 1) proceed
from a good state, 2) lead to a good state, or 3), lead from one good state to
another. Each of these three types
of action is an action of unification.
Indeed, it could be said in general that a good action is a unifying
action.
It
is most clear that actions which lead from one good state to another are good
because unification is verified at both ends of the actions. Actions, however, which do not arise
out of a good state or condition and which nevertheless produce such are
clearly producing the result by unifying something. Furthermore, in starting out from a
good state, an action carries something of unity with it. In other words, an action that starts
out from a bad state may produce a good one, and an action which ends in a bad
state may have started out from a good one. It is also true, in the concrete, that good beginnings, as
well as good endings, are not necessarily pure goods. Evil, as we have observed, is a disruption, and an acting
being can disrupt itself or others.
Thus, by way of illustration, an action can proceed from some kind of
strength that the actor (acting being) uses to tear itself down, or the result
of an action may be good for the actor and not for others.
Although
I suppose that there could be cosmological applications of this analysis of
good action, I am not sure that consideration of them would be more than idle
speculation, but applications of the analysis to human actions are far from
idle. We distinguished above three
kinds of human unity: organic, intentional, and social. Good human actions will arise from or
lead to one or more of these kinds of unity in human life, and they will avoid
introducing evils
In
view of this it is proper to say that many and varied kinds of human actions
can be analyzed as good or evil.
It suffices to think of good digestion and bad headaches. At the head of this section, however,
we saw that only some human actions are to be considered from an ethical point
of view: they are the actions of the whole person, of the self. Therefore ethics is the study of how
actions of the whole self foster or disrupt in one or the other of the three
ways mentioned the three kinds of human unity spoken of. Not all the logical combinations which
derive from plotting organic unity, intentional unity, and social unity against
actions proceeding from good states, actions leading to good states, and
actions proceeding from and leading to good states qualify as ethical, but some
of them can do. Thus,
Actions
proceeding from organic unity are not candidates for ethical goodness because
they lack the conscious self. On
the contrary, actions proceeding from intentional unity involve the conscious
self and some goodness which is in it.
Actions proceeding from social unity are coming from goodness
consciously shared by many individuals.
Actions which lead to organic unity of the individual procure
significant good for it, which it perceives. So do, and more so, actions which lead to the individual's
intentional unity, which is conscious unity of feelings and emotions. Lastly, actions leading to social unity
bring about a state of common good which is perceived by the individuals
included in it. From this analysis
it appears that many types of human action are susceptible of being ethical.
Mark
Johnson, in Moral Imagination: Implication of Cognitive Science for Ethics,
starts from a strong anti-rationalist position that ethics is not a body of
universal rational principles, but is "... a matter of how well or how
poorly we construct (i.e., live out) a narrative that solves our problem of
living a meaningful and significant life." (p.180) Life is like a story that we tell about
ourselves, and his main interest is in the metaphorical language we use to tell
the story. In practice, "We strive for unity in our lives
by situating our present acts within our history and by projecting ourselves
into a future that somehow partly blends together our multiple understandings,
values, and purposes." (p. 164)
This is, it would seem, not too different from the present essay's
analysis of ethical action.
We
have now acquired a structure for understanding the basic relationships between
the variously proposed norms of ethics.
First, there are norms that refer to an action's proceeding from a good
state, and these can be called antecedent norms. Then there are norms that refer to the
action's being productive of a good state, and these could be called consequent
norms, but in practice they are termed consequentialist (or
teleological) norms. One of the
antecedent norms, that of good intention, is called deontological. In recent philosophical history there
has been a great battle between deontologism, and consequentialism, as though
one or the other is the more fundamental.
A metaphysical view such as the one I am proposing, on the contrary,
gives each its due and makes clear the relationships between the two. The narrow recent state of the question
makes it difficult to fit into the discussion the remaining norms which refer
to actions' proceeding from a good state.
This, it seems to me, is a loss for philosophy which can be avoided by
following a procedure such as mine.
Secondly,
there are ethical actions which are from or toward the good of the individual
and there are ethical actions which are from or toward the good of
society. This distinction raises
questions of precedence of the individual over society or of society over the
individual. Are norms of ethics
more appropriately found in the individual or in society? Some cultures, such as that of the
United States, favor ideological solutions based on the individual, while other
cultures, including some continental European ones, favor basing such solutions
on the society, not only as to outcomes but even as to a starting point of
collective thinking. My approach,
I think, makes it possible to give due weight to both the individual and society.
Again,
there are ethical norms which refer to the person's own entity as being good
and there are those which refer to the particular starting point of actions as
being good. This is a matter of
the relationship between the good person and the good actions of the person,
between virtue and good intention.
Virtue ethics seem to be coming back into vogue in American ethics, and
it is useful to see how virtues relate to the well established ethics of good
intention.
The
positive interrelations between virtue, deontological, and teleological norms
have been recognized as far back as Socrates, the founder of western
ethics. Socrates extracted from
earlier Greek thought about virtue the notion of virtue (arete) as the
valor or strength of people, and he observed that the particular virtues acknowledged
before him (especially courage, justice, and wisdom) had a common element, good,
and that a person becomes good only by action which is directed at a goal, and
through obeying his own inner voice (daimonion). Socrates himself did not profess to know what the good was,
but sought it and taught others to so the same. (Bruno Snell, The Discovery of the Mind in Greek
Philosophy and Literature, Chapter 8, ÒThe Call to Virtue: A Brief Chapter
from Greek Ethics,Ó pp. 153-190.)
In
common speech we refer to ethical ÒfeelingsÓ or ethical Òsentiments,Ó and we
speak as though we were guided by these feelings, as though they were norms of
ethical conduct. No responsible
ethicist, as far as I am aware, has maintained a totally non-cognitive
position, that is, that ethical feelings are unrelated to the intentions and/or
the outcomes of action. Such a
position on the part of someone would, of course, be completely
unassailable. Unfortunately,
however, so would the position of another individual whose feelings were
different from those of the first person.
I do not want to emphasize this exercise in logic, but I could put it
this way: in the supposition that pure feelings are ethical norms, there is no
room for ethical discourse, no possibility for intellectual interchange in the
matter, no topic which could be called Òethics.Ó
A
word closely associated in common parlance with ethical norms and their
application is conscience.
In the sense that conscience is our perception of the ethics of a
situation, of the norms we apply to it, conscience is a helpful notion, albeit
not a necessary one. The term is
extended to refer to our condition after ethical action: we say that we have a
good conscience or a bad one depending on whether or not we have acted in
accordance with our perception of the norms. Having a bad conscience is also described as having a sense
of guilt, although there is no corresponding description for having a good
conscience. Historically, the term
conscience has had the technical meaning of the ÒfacultyÓ of making
ethical judgments on the one hand and of the daimonion, or imperious
internal voice telling us how to act, on the other. Currently it is used to describe our immediate ethical
inclinations or feelings when these seem stronger to us than the ethical
reasons for them seem, and psychologically this is a useful meaning of the term
as long as it is not taken to deny that there are ethical reasons or norms
Responsibility
As
stated above, the good or the bad action comes from the human person as a
whole. As the possessor of the
good or bad initial state of the action, or, as it is more commonly put, as the
author of the action, the person is said to be responsible or accountable for
the action; the action is imputable to the person. This person is at least potentially deserving of praise or
blame, possibly of reward or punishment.
These latter consequences of actions or reactions to them will be
considered in the section on sanction. Our attention in the present section is on responsibility or
accountability. This introductory assertion expresses concepts which have a
certain theoretical interest in any treatment of general ethics. In our immediate context, for instance,
they situate the matter of responsibility in the framework of the good/bad
action analysis. They are even
more important in the application of general ethical theory to concrete
applications, the human relations of which include the knowledge of how involved
persons are with their ethical actions and what, if anything, will happen to
them because of these actions.
The
conditions of ethical responsibility are whatever it takes for the person to
enter into a good or bad action.
The background condition is clearly the ability to apprehend the
action, to know or understand it as the bridge between two states. This being the case, there is the basic
condition, which is the ability or power to place the action, to do it. In addition to this it is necessary to
be able to apply ethical norms to the action. These three conditions are sufficient in a completely
deterministic theory of human action.
I, however, have taken a stand against complete determinism and have
asserted that humans are free at least to the extent that they can act or not
act. This being the case, a fourth
condition of ethical action is that the person, upon evaluating the action
ethically, acts or does not act.
At
this point we can say either that responsibility occurs when all four conditions
are satisfied or that it is lacking when they are not satisfied. The difference between these two
perspectives is a matter of the philosophy of people and society: can we hold
that one or the other, the state of responsibility or of irresponsibility, is
the more common among us? We shall
avoid this question by pointing to actions that are prima facie good or bad and
asking to what extent the conditions of responsibility are satisfied.
The
first condition of ethical responsibility, apprehension of an action, means
that the person apprehends the entirety of an action, that is, of two states
and an activity which connects them.
This is not an ethical evaluation; it is an awareness of self in some
relationship to a state of affairs that is yet to happen. In common descriptive terms this means
that the person knows what he or she is doing.
The
next condition, the power to act, to bring about a new state of affairs, is in
itself not distinctively human.
Rather, it is characteristic of the dynamism of beings in general. We, however, unlike other beings around
us, can be aware of this power; we can reflect on it. An exercise of power is present no matter what results from
the action. Even a change within
the person, without any exterior result, is a new state, and arriving at it
involves some exercise of power.
Being totally stymied, party to a total non-action, is different from
this.
Application
of ethical norms, the third condition, can range from unquestioning
concentration on one norm to careful reflection on many. We have yet in this essay to compare
norms and ask which are most suitable in various types of action. Preliminarily, we may suppose that a
single-norm evaluation will generally not be adequate to deal with all the
facets of an ethical situation, but whether this is true or not, the acting
person can be ethically responsible only to the extent that the same is aware
of ethical issues. The
psychological question of the possibility of there being a totally amoral
person arises here: are there people who are not aware of ethical issues? This is different from seeing the
issues and always, if this is possible, choosing the evil.
The
final condition, the decision, given all the above, to act or not to act, is
the focal point of ethical responsibility. It is the moment of human freedom in action, the moment
when, seeing more than one course of action and seeing that no course is
compelling, we choose in default of being forced to choose. Without this instant of
self-determination we would indeed be complex automatons going our way in this
world, rather than people.
Describing this freedom in detail is a task for the philosophy of people
and society, and I did that in my chapter on metaphysics. We can nevertheless, point to a
conclusion about responsibility which Mortimer Adler derives from his study of
freedom in The Idea of Freedom (vol I, p. 617): "The generic
meaning of responsibility would seem to have the same roots as the generic
meaning of freedom. As a man is
free only in doing that which is his own action or in achieving that
which is proper to himself, so a man is responsible only for the actions
or achievements that are his own or proper to him. He is not
answerable or accountable for that which is done by another or belongs to
another; nor can such things be imputed to him. Hence, no matter how man's freedom is conceived in detail,
he will be conceived to be responsible in whatever way and to whatever extent
he is conceived to be free."
At
this point there is a fork in the road of the study of ethics. Many ethicists are interested only in
understanding and applying the norms.
These are not only theoretical ethicists; their number includes
practical ethicists who do not want to pass judgment on others. Others, however, want to know how
responsible people are for the good or evil that proceeds from their actions,
and it seems to me that we at least need to allude to this if we want to have
the whole picture of how ethics relates to the real world. Looking ahead to real-life situations,
we can readily see that the first three conditions of responsibility are
susceptible to many influences.
Apprehension of an action as a whole and perception of one's ability to
do it are not necessarily simple matters.
The range of ethical norms one has available to apply to a situation,
whether any situation or this situation reflects many factors in
a person's life.
Furthermore, as to the fourth condition, there are complications such as
our ability to hold back from realizing or creating the indeterminacy that
would be required for us to act freely: we may not be strong enough; we may
feel that we do not have a right to it.
(Becker, The Structure of Evil.) Thus, a judgment about responsibility in the concrete
particular is daunting and not lightly to be undertaken, no matter how sure we
are of our ethical principles.It is most likely tobe called for in ethics, as
it is in law, is we have to deal with sanction.
Sanction
Ethical
sanction is the consequence to the actor for responsibly placing an ethical
action; presumably positive sanction (reward) for good actions and negative
sanction (punishment) for bad ones.
The rewards and punishments of human legal and social sanction are, of course,
very similar to this, but they apply to actions strictly according to their
effects in society and not according to their ethical character. Ethical sanction is mentioned less in
ethical treatises than it is in moral exhortations and polemics.
Applying
the notion of ethical sanction, we can readily see that several kinds of it are
said to exist:
1.
Hedonistic or eudaemonistic, bringing pleasure or happiness or their opposite
to one's self by one's action.
2.
Virtue as its own reward; vice as leading to unhappiness and despair. This is understood mainly to be peace
of conscience or the remorse of a bad conscience.
3.
Perfection arising out of action.
This is perhaps no more than a fusion of the first two, but it is
conceptually different from either of them, and, furthermore, the lack of
perfection seems to be a weak negative sanction.
In the above, the sanction
is intrinsic to the action.
4.
Utilitarian or just (that is, according to justice), bringing pleasure or
happiness or their opposite to society.
This kind of sanction is intrinsic to the action if the actor benefits
from it, which need not be the case.
5.
God rewards or punishes.
6.
Society rewards or punishes. We
must be careful to distinguish this from legal or social sanction. It is more a matter of feelings of
belonging (positive sanction) and of guilt (negative sanction) than of
applications of law and custom.
The
final two kinds of sanction are extrinsic to the ethical action as such.
It
is clearly possible that one action, good or bad, will call forth many kinds of
sanction, possibly even all of them.
It is also clear that sanction can relate to either terminus of the
action or to the action as a whole.
Furthermore, it is said that acting precisely because of sanction is not
ethically as good as acting because of the moral norm which implies the
sanction. (By contrast, if you act
because of legal sanction you are acting as legally as you are for any other
motive.) This last consideration,
however, appears to arise from perfectionism, and as such is not of general
interest. In short, ethical
sanction is a complex phenomenon, and it is not reducible to one or another
aspect of ethical norms.
Further
speculation can lead us to ask, what if intrinsic or at least foreseen sanction
is not proportioned to the good or the evil of the action or is outright
contrary to it? This does not seem
to be a particularly vexing question if the disproportion is not substantial,
but if it is substantial - for instance, if one has dedicated a whole life to
unselfish service of others with little pleasure or recompense from it and, in the end, is disgraced,
banished, or even executed by those who had received the benefits. Again, what about a person who has
brought about misery and death for thousands or millions of people and who
lives and dies peacefully? It is
quite possible to ignore these questions in a treatment of ethics, because, it
must be remembered, ethics is concerned with the suitability of human actions. These questions, nevertheless, are
imperious, and they need to be answered
or at least considered somewhere - if not in ethics, then in philosophy
of people and society.
We
could turn the questions around and look at them from another angle if we ask, ÒWhy
should sanction be qualitatively like the action (positive for positive,
negative for negative), and why should it be quantitatively proportioned to the
action?Ó It appears to be a matter
of justice and fairness. Now, one
might suppose that justice and fairness call for definitive sanction that is
not left up to the vagaries of people and the whims of chance, but how would
one prove this? It seems to me
that this is one of the instances in which philosophy has to question common
thinking, at least the thinking common in our culture.
In
the western religious supposition that there is a personal God who is just and
fair with creatures, it would be iniquitous of this God not to reward or punish
people according to their deserts.
Much as people would like to think, however, that virtue is its own
reward, etc., most religious people admit that God does not generally reward or
punish in this life, and they hold that God does so in the afterlife. (As a matter of fact, the lack of
sanction in this life has been taken as an argument for the very existence of
God.) Since the present essay is
not theological, I mention this viewpoint but I do not promote it in a study of
ethics for a multicultural society.
Another
approach to definitive sanction
lies in the Karma of Indian philosophy: to pass through successive
existences until one has attained the best state that one possibly can and then
to have the reward for this, whether it be absorption in Brahman or the
cessation of all desire. This is
neither a matter of the activity of people nor of irrational chance; it
embodies the worldview of a universe which is not rational in a Western sense,
but which possesses an inexorable dynamism.
In
a Western non-religious supposition definitive sanction is easily thinkable if
it is the case that the good one does builds up the goodness of the person and
the evil one does tears down this goodness. If then there is an afterlife, the quality of it will
presumably be affected by the amount of goodness or oneness a person had when
emerging from the present life.
This might be called the ultimate triumph of intrinsic sanction. I am not aware of anyone who proposes
this view of sanction from philosophical premises.
At
least one additional possibility remains concerning the need for just and fair
definitive sanction. We have been
measuring the good and evil of human actions by a limited standard: how much benefit or harm is done to the
actor or to the people immediately concerned, or even, in some cases, to large
segments of society? These are
finite quantities, even if some of them are large in the human context. If, however, we consider the whole of the universe the good or evil that
people can do is infinitesimal, and therefore there is no measurable disorder
or imbalance to be rectified by sanctions introduced from outside the course of
human affairs in the present life.
This is the case whether or not there is an afterlife.
Finally,
if there is no such thing as definitive sanction, either because there is no
need for it or because there is no
afterlife in which to administer it, acting ethically is not doomed to ultimate
frustration. Nozick, in Philosophical
Explanations introduces the question of the meaning of life and existence,
especially human, by observing that living ethically seems to be pointless if
it accomplishes nothing in the long run (p. 570), but he leaves the question
with the thought that the search for meaning and value is valuable in itself.
Collective Ethical Action
So
far in this chapter we have clearly been examining ethics from the point of
view of the action of human individuals, but there is also the matter of
collective human action.
There is no question here of collective actionÕs being good or bad, that
is, subject to evaluation by ethical norms. Of course it is - at least by
consequentialist norms, which are clearly applicable to the outcomes of
collective action. One can ask,
however, if there are collective intentions, collective attitudes which might
be called virtues, or collective worldviews? A descriptive ethics of collective action exists notably in
political criticism, in which people of varied backgrounds (including, but in a
minor way, philosophy) express their opinion of the goodness or badness of
political parties, governments, and whole countries. Abundant literature on this matter is provided by analyses
of the responsibility for war and for excesses associated with war. A prime recent example is German
responsibility for World War II and the slaughter of the Jews.
Among
the many studies of German responsibility is one by the German philosopher Karl
Jaspers. In this work, The
Question of German Guilt, the philosopher is being concrete rather than
abstract. There are, however,
useful intellectual distinctions which belong in empirical description before
they are assimilated by philosophical systematizing. Cognizance of the four kinds of guilt he acknowledges (pp.
31-32 and following) clarifies thinking on the subject. Criminal guilt is in the public
forum of laws, moral guilt is in the internal forum of conscience, political
guilt is that of a country and is imputed to all its citizens, who stand or
fall with their country, and metaphysical guilt is the co-responsibility
of all humans for evil caused by the human race. Without developing these distinctions at all, Jaspers points
out that, according to them, only political guilt applies to the collectivity,
"But in addition there is our moral guilt. Although this always burdens only the individual who must
get along with himself, there still is a sort of collective morality contained
in the ways of life and feeling, from which no individual can altogether escape
and which have political significance as well.... We feel something like a co-responsibility for the acts of
members of our families. This
co-responsibility cannot be objectivized.
We should reject any manner of tribal liability. And yet, because of our consanguinity
we are inclined to feel concerned whenever wrong is done by someone in the
family..." (pp.78-79)
A
philosophical approach to the question about collective intentions, etc. is to
ask if there is such an entity as a collective person which would
perforce have collective intentions, attitudes, and worldviews. Phenomenology seems particularly suited
to this line of thinking because it makes no presuppositions about the
phenomenological observer being a discrete individual: the observer may just as
well be an element of a collective person. Max Scheler has pursued this line of phenomenological
description in several works, and applies it especially to ethics in Formalism
in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values, in which he states, "Just
as the person discovers every psychic experience against the cogiven background
of a stream of such experiences, and every object of outer perception against
the background of and as a 'part' of a nature that is spatially and temporally
endless, so also in every execution of an act is the person given to himself in
self-experience as a member of a community of persons which encompasses
him. Whatever the type of this
community, simultaneity and succession (of generations) are at first still undifferentiated. From an ethical viewpoint this
experience of a person's necessary membership in a social sphere appears in the
coresponsibility for the total effective activity of the sphere. With regard to the possible factualness
of community, it appears in re-experiencing and coexperiencing, refeeling
and cofeeling, as the basic acts of inner perception of the other. At least the very sense of
community and its possible existence is not an assumption that requires
empirical establishment, because in certain classes of acts the intention
toward a possible community is cogiven by essential necessity with the
nature of these acts themselves.
It is, rather, an assumption that is conjoined with the sense of a person
as originally and essentially as it is with that of the outer and
inner worlds." (p. 519)
Again, "It is therefore in the person that the mutually
related individual person and collective person become
differentiated. The idea of one is
not the 'foundation' of the other. The collective or group person is not
composed of individual persons in the sense that it derives its existence from
such a composition; nor is the collective person a result of the merely
reciprocal agency of individual persons or (subjectively and in cognition) a
result of a synthesis of arbitrary additions. It is an experienced reality,
and not a construction, although it is a starting point for constructions of
all types." (p. 522) Because
of what Scheler calls the "principle of solidarity," which is
"... the original coresponsibility of every person for the moral
salvation of the whole of all realms of persons (p. xxiv), we must ask,
"What of positive moral value would have occurred in the world and what of
negative moral value would have been avoided if I as a representative of a
place in the social structure, had comported myself differently? But everyone must also ask, What would
have occurred if I, as a spiritual individual, had grasped, willed, and
realized the 'good-in-itself-for-me' ... in a superior manner?
(p. 534) In general, pages 519 to
561 of this work treat this, but Scheler's longer as well as his best known
work dealing with it, in a non-ethical context, is The Nature of Sympathy.
It
is not clear to me that analyses such as SchelerÕs lead to a demonstration of
collective intention which can be evaluated ethically. Furthermore, he observes that the
RousseauÕs notion of the general will (The Social Contract, Book
I, Chapter 7, Book II, Chapters 1,3,and 6) has never won general acceptance as
a workable description of a force in society. The existence of collective
intention would have to be shown empirically in order to allow sufficient
agreement for people to discuss its ethics. Public intention can be shown by such processes as
voting, but this is a political, not a moral process. For these reasons I would not propose ethical norm number
14, ÒCommon Will,Ó as a norm to be used in a pluralistic environment.
SchelerÕs
and JaspersÕs observations, nevertheless, describe a solidarity of attitude
which is analogous to individual virtue: an attitude that permeates a group (or
organization or society) and is conveyed by its internal shared public media as
being the attitude expected of individuals in that group. The writer would not hesitate to speak
of particular collective virtues in a group if this served to clarify the
ethical analysis of the groupÕs action.
Thus, for example, a law, which is the expression of a political
intention, can show that there is a spirit of benevolence or conscientiousness
in a society or that such a spirit is lacking.
The
precise question which is most often considered here is not about collective
goodness or evil, but about collective responsibility: is a group responsible
for its actions? are individuals responsible for group actions? if so, in
either case, to what extent? This
question should not be oversimplified; judging the responsibility of a group of
three people on a sidewalk is worlds apart from judging the actions of a whole
society. Between these extremes
lie communities, corporations, churches, and other kinds of groups of varying
levels of complexity. Judging the
legal responsibilities of such organizations is important to their members and
to those whose lives they affect, and the law does this. It is not immediately clear how close
the legal procedure is to a moral procedure of determining responsibility, but
there is enough said about the so-called moral responsibility of groups that
the topic needs to be brought under scrutiny.
The
responsibility of societies as a whole has been a topic of political philosophy
since ancient times. Particularly
influential have been Plato's The Republic and Rousseau's The Social
Contract. For an introductory
notion in the present context about these two as well as the Englishman, F.H.
Bradley, see Peter French, Collective and Corporate Responsibility, pp.
94-111.
The
responsibility of business corporations and/or their members has been an area
of concern of modern business ethicists, and it has led to a wealth of
investigation and intellectual exchange in a practical context. For a
bibliography on corporate responsibility in the business world see Velasquez, Business
Ethics, pp. 18, 42, and 43.
Following
the train of thought of this essay, and summarizing the arguments both from
political philosophy and business ethics, it ought to be possible to determine
the presence of corporate responsibility by asking how the conditions of
responsibility are verified: apprehension of an action, power to act,
application of norms, decision to act or not to act. The least examination of these, however, shows that it is
more difficult to recognize these conditions in group action than it is in
individual action. The very first
condition is lacking unless there is an accurate flow of information through
the ranks of the corporation to the decision makers. Furthermore, various people involved in making a decision
may have competing views on the norms which apply, and the decision to act can
be a complex action which includes many single decisions. Among recent authors Patricia Werhane
argues against speaking of corporate responsibility as we speak of individual
responsibility in Persons, Rights, & Corporations, but Peter French
proposes a way of saying that we can do this in Collective and Corporate
Responsibility.
Two
useful works on collective responsibility, paarticularly relating to business,
in addition to French's, are The Morality of Groups by Larry May and Collective
Responsibility, edited by Larry May and Stacey Hoffman. In his own work May, like French, takes
the position that there is such a thing a corporate responsibility which is
different from the total of individual responsibilities, and both authors
develop lines of argumentation that are similar to the one briefly outlined
above by the writer of this essay.
Both cite classical and contemporary philosophers, French more the
former and May more the latter. A
key quote from May is "The thesis of this book is that the structure
of social groups plays such an important role in the acts, intentions, and
interests of members of groups, that social groups should be given a moral
status different from that of the discrete individual persons who compose
them. Thus, the chief target of
this book is the thesis that the moral standing of social groups is no
different from the aggregate moral standing of individual, isolated persons. But I am also critical of those
theorists who see the social group as having a moral standing completely
separate from the discrete individual persons who constitute the group. The structure of a social group is the
set of relationships that exist among the group's members. While these relationships make for
different acts, intentions, and interests than would exist outside the group,
nonetheless they are relationships of individual persons." (p.
3.). May and Hoffman's collection
of articles is arranged in part like a debate between supporters and opponents
of their position. Two of the
articles in it, one by Hannah Arendt, center on particular historical events,
the mass murders of civilians by German forces in World War II and the less
extensive, but nevertheless large scale murder of Vietnamese civilians by
American forces in the U.S. Vietnamese War.
It
strikes me that the mere assigning of corporate responsibility, difficult as it
may be, is of practical value only if its consequences can be correctly
described. What happens, we should
ask, if a corporation is ethically responsible for its actions? This is not like legal responsibility,
in consideration of which corporations are punished if they are responsible for
acting illegally and, in some sense, pehaps, rewarded if they are responsible
for acting legally. Sanction for
the ethical actions of corporations consists of the good or bad opinion people,
individually or collectively, have of them and the actions to which this
opinion leads. A bad opinion, for
instance, can mean that a corporation's products or services are
boycotted. It can also mean that
people do not want to work for the organization. If a corporation is punished physically, that is, by fines
or dismemberment, this is always, as far as I know, legal action taken by some
legal power. This description of
the meaning of corporate responsibility fits neatly with the loathing we have
of making ethical judgments in the business world: it is both easier and less
dangerous to make legal judgments.
Whatever
can be said about group responsibility, it does not take away the individual
responsibility of persons who take an active role in executing the collective
ethical action. It is true that in
the reality of large scale collective action, business or political, many
individuals have such insignificant roles or have such little understanding of
their part in the action that they do not have individual reponsibility. Still, this is not always the case, and
there are decision makers who have to be considered responsible for the collective
decisions, and there are workers who know that what they are expected to do
cannot be part of an overall good ethical action. The rationalization that the worker is ethically free to do
whatever ordered by the corporation is based on the false premise that the only
ethical norm the worker, called, in this instance, the loyal agent, need be
concerned with is the utilitarian good of the corporation. (Velasquez, Business Ethics,
treats this in pp. 18-25 and 42-45.
Velasquez borrows the "loyal agent's argument" from Alex C.
Michales, "The Loyal Agent's Argument," in Ethical Theory and
Business by Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie.)
DESCRIPTIVE ETHICS
Descriptive
ethics is the description of what is said to be ethical or not ethical by
various human groups. The first
set of groups one thinks of in this regard is the set of human societies or
cultures, the "peoples' of the world, present and past. Cultural anthropology has paid less
attention to the ethical thought and practices of peoples than it has to many
other facets of societal life, but it has not been altogether lacking, and
there is a body of knowledge called comparative ethics, which deals with them.
Comparative ethics as a science dates back to Auguste Comte, who decided some
time after his initial work of the 1830s that it could be included in social
physics or sociology as a branch that was concerned with specific aspects of
human behavior. (Copleston, A
History of Philosophy, vol. 9, pp. 84-85.)
A
second set of human groups to be studied in descriptive ethics consists of
sectors of society with distinctive shared ethical views or shared ethical
problems associated with distinctive activities. Such groups as physicians and politicians have undergone
ethical analysis of their activities since time immemorial. In Western society health care ethics,
legal ethics, and business ethics have recently come to the fore. In our day, too, many researchers apply
the methods of social science research to ascertain what these groups regard as
ethical matters and how they are divided statistically in their stances on
them.
Children
and adults in identifiable stages of development of ethical thinking are the
third set of groups which are being studied empirically under the heading of
developmental ethics. The validity
of the data and the consequent interpretation of the data in this field are not
yet firmly established, but some points will be made about them below.
Ethics
in literature can be considered a subset of descriptive ethics, and I end
this chapter with a few observations about ethics as found in literary works.
Comparative ethics
French
social philosophers advanced Comte's approach to ethics. Thus, toward the end of the nineteenth
century ƒmile Durkheim approached comparative ethics by freeing it from Comte's
philosophical system and insisting that moral facts exist only in the several
social contexts of humankind. A
few years into the twentieth century Lucien LŽvy-Bruhl treated ethics very like
Durkheim except that he was a little more philosophically inclined. He proposed that once the descriptive
data were collected some philosophical interpretation could be made of them
without invoking a priori philosophical norms. (Copleston, A History of Philosophy. vol 9, pp.
123-124 and 130-31.)
In
the first decades of the twentieth century American ethnologists, led by Franz
Boas and followed by such well known names as Ruth Benedict and Margaret Mead,
engaged in cultural anthropology
with a scientific method that intentionally avoided making ethical
pronouncements about the peoples they were studying, and they even tended to
stay clear of the study of the ethical views of their subjects. Nevertheless, observations which, in
the spirit of Comte, could be assembled in the format of comparative ethics
were not lacking, and the assembling has been accomplished by a number of
authors. The writer refers
particularly to the anthropologists May Edel, Anthropology and Ethics,
and Raymond Firth, Elements of Social Organization, and the philosophers
Abraham Edel, Anthropology and Ethics, Alexander Macbeath, Experiments
in Living, and Samuel Fleischacker, The Ethics of Culture.
Philosophers
cannot expect cultural anthropologists to analyze the ethics of peoples in the
terms of particular philosophical systems. The approach of the anthropologists has to be that of
examining a certain set of observable data in as unbiased a way as possible. In a very general way it seems safe to
say that rules of individual conduct with public aspects, with dimensions of
right and wrong action, of good and bad people, and with attached sanctions are
found everywhere. More
specifically, Fleishacker writes of "... a fairly strong, but still
minimal, set of conditions for anything to count as a morality or ethical code:
it must be action guiding, ideal based, overridingly important, directed toward
a conceivable end, accompanied by a conception of 'personhood' that does not
severely conflict with our own, and not aimed toward the degradation or
destruction of any being fitting that conception of 'person.'" (The
Ethics of Culture, p. 19.)
The
full complexity of the task is shown by Edel and Edel: "We know that, for
any morality we wish to understand in depth, we must know not only the content
of its moral rules, the virtues it approves and the kind of behavior it
deplores, the goals or ideals it cherishes, but we must also map its position
along many other, more purely structural, axes. We must note whether its injunctions are imperative, or
mildly advisory; what kind of terms it uses for moral appraisals; whether it
stresses ideals, or models, or rules.
Do many of life's aims and goals come into the morality, or does
conscious moral emphasis play only a limited cultural role? Are its formulations abstract and
generalized, or highly specific, and differentiated according to kinship or
other relationships or situations?
Is it concerned primarily with individual behavior and individual
responsibility, or are there conscious reflections about group goals or 'social
policy?' Are its sanctions rooted
in automatic retributions, human or divine? Is moral education verbalized and explicit? Are there strong emotional commitments
in the moral field? Are moral
decisions often necessary, and how are they mediated - through officials, or
objective techniques, or reckoning of consequences in human relations? Does public pressure play a large
role? Does it take the form of
punishment, or ridicule, or compulsion or advice? And so on and on and on." (Anthropology and Ethics. pp. 192-93.)
An
example of a modern cultural anthropologist who examines the morals of the
people he studies is Meyer Fortes, who, in one of his later works on the
Tallensi of Ghana, considers the morals, the religious beliefs, and the
perception of the world with a studied dispassion and abhorrence of bias. He defines good and evil in general:
"Tallensi culture is marked by the propensity to conserve and contain. The
good is identified with what is conserved and contained, evil with what must be
cast out of the family and the community." (p.206) He states that good ritual is
"ritual that has collective authorization" and bad ritual "is
secret and antisocial and is supported by collusion not consensus."
(p.7) He remarks (p. 69) that a
complete analysis of ancestor worship such as that of the Tallensi "... is
a branch of religion and of moral philosophy, not to speak of its functions as
a theory of causation." A
number of times he mentions moral good and evil: incest prohibition (p. 71),
patri-filial relations (p. 73), the moral component of societies, i.e.,
"the mutual commitment to his roles of person and society focused in
status and office." (p. 105), "It is morally polluting and mystically
dangerous to shed any human blood upon the Earth, even when it is lawful in
self-help or warfare. Killing, except for food or sacrifice, is felt to be a
sin. (p. 135), envy, greed, hate, and malice are bad (p. 212), procreation of a
first born is a moral duty (p. 232), good-for-nothings, thieves, and adulterers
are bad (p. 275), adultery with a father's wife is bad (p. 278). He does not take a stance on what moral
good and evil are, but, rather, seems to assume that he and his readers
share a notion of moral good and evil, and none of his examples call for some
special ethical theory to explain why they are good or bad.
For
the purposes of the present chapter it will be sufficient to point to a few
aspects of the above. Areas of
human activity in which it seems that all societies have moral norms are:
nurture of children, selection of sexual partners, control of in-group
aggression, rules for in-group communicating, reliability (promises and
contracts), return for services rendered, and distribution of goods within the
social unit. (Edel and Edel, Anthropology
and Ethics, chapters IV to VII, pp. 34-76; Firth, Elements of Social
Organization, pp. 190-203; Macbeath, Experiments in Living, chapters
IV through VIII, pp. 103-268, in which he compares the ethics of four peoples, showing
differences as well as similarities.)
As
we look at the details of the ethical codes of various peoples we immediately
see their differences. How to
raise children? how to conduct sexual union? which kinds of people ought to be
killed and which kinds ought not? what is truth? what is property? are
questions with astoundingly diverse answers. (Macbeath, Experiments in Living, and Fleischacker, The
Ethics of Culture, are more concerned with the differences than with the
similarities and give an abundance of examples.)
In
the concrete, some examples of practices which are unethical in Western
culture, but which are judged to be ethical in their own cultures are the Bantu
practice of killing one of twins at birth (to stop the evil forces which arise from
the birth of twins), the Australian Aborigine custom of lending one's wife to a
visitor (as a gesture of hospitality), and the Chucksee prescription for
killing one's father "before he loses his vigour and vitality"
(because of the belief "that a man will continue for ever in the state in
which he is at the time of his death"). (Macbeath, Experiments in Living, pp. 169, 217, and
365-6.)
In
cases of peoples who accord an important role to black magic and sorcery, to
whom the imparting of information "provides them with the means of using
these powers, we have a state of affairs in which not mutual trust and
confidence but mutual suspicion and fear are likely to flourish. In such circumstances, truth-telling is
not likely to be regarded as a virtue except in situations like giving evidence
in court, where truth-telling is likely to result in good to others and lying
in harm to them." (Macbeath,
pp. 372-73.)
Another
good example of the differences in ethical codes is the non-universality of the
Lockean concept of private property.
Witness the statement of Black Hawk, the American Indian warrior who in
1832 led a rebellion against the European Americans as they appropriated
traditional Indian lands: "My
reason teaches me that land cannot be sold. The Great Spirit gave it to
his children to live upon, and cultivate, as far as is necessary for their
subsistence; and so long as they occupy and cultivate it, they have the right
to the soil - but if they voluntarily leave it, then any other people have a right
to settle upon it. Nothing can be
sold, but such things as can be carried away." (Black Hawk: an Autobiography, p.101.)
The
diversity of views of the individual in relation to society: to see one's self
as an autonomous individual as opposed to seeing self as an element in a
collectivity of persons has many implications for ethics. Modern Western individualism versus
Marxism comes to mind before we even begin to look farther afield in space and
time. The history of the Western
notion of rights is also an apt illustration of such implications.
In
spite of the differences in ethics between cultures, there appear to be some
valid generalizations about comparative ethics. Indiscriminate killing, indiscriminate coitus,
indiscriminate appropriation of material objects seem to be wrong
everywhere. The apparent truth of
such generalizations tempts one to derive ethical rules from comparative
ethics, but this endeavor is beset by many problems. Simply accepting the generalizations as supreme ethical
principles does not, it is pointed out, tell which killing is right or
wrong. Thus Macbeath writes,
My
contention is that the ambiguity of the terms used, the great variety of the
ways in which the rules are construed by different peoples and of the exceptions
which they admit to the rules which they recognize, show that the rules lack
the definiteness and precision necessary to self-evident intuitions; and that
the rightness of the rules themselves, in
those cases in which they are recognized as right, the ways in which
they are construed, the exceptions to them which are regarded as justified, and
the relative order of urgency which is assigned to them, are explicable by, and
derive their authority from, the way of life of the people concerned. In other words, they have not a
rightness which is independent of the goodness of the state of affairs whose
conditions they are. (Macbeath, Experiments
in Living, pp. 369-70.)
Another
way of looking at the problem is to ask if we can reason to universal ethical
principles by heaping up similarities in the ethical practices of peoples. This process is attractive because it
appears to be scientific, and it seemingly ought to produce the laws of human
conduct as an instance of the scientific induction which gives us the laws of
physics and chemistry. In
addition, however, to the weakness of the principles that, as we have just
seen, can be derived by this method, ethical action, as seen by those who
act, while they act, has a subjective component, and no principle of ethics
which ignores this component does justice to the phenomenon of ethics. (This is alluded to by Fleischacker in The
Ethics of Culture, chapter 1.)
Still,
some observations about the cultural variants of ethics lead to
incontrovertible concrete statements which must have some universal
validity. Thus, although some
societies approve of infanticide, it could scarcely be approvable as a practice
at all times and places. Or,
"Any way of life whose general structure or scale of value does not admit
of being extended to mankind as a whole, without denying the common humanity of
some men and their right to be treated as persons" will have to be
changed. An example is of Crow Indians, whose social structure was built around
bellicosity. (Macbeath, Experiments
in Living, p. 436.)
It
appears to me that comparative ethics leads to solid generalizations. Thus, codes of conduct everywhere serve
to preserve a society and, further, to protect it from change. They also furnish the individual with
clearcut expectations of how to be the kind of individual which the society
wants. More specific rules of
conduct, nearly universal ones, apply to transculturally similar situations
involving the areas in which all societies seem to have moral norms as
mentioned above. The mental
process by which we go from empirical codes of conduct to ethical norms is
philosophical, and the philosophical value of comparative ethics is to prevent
us from making foolish, chauvinistic errors.
The
bridge between comparative and philosophical ethics could be expressed in more
than one way, but the words of Fleischacker show how this can be done even by
one who is adamantly opposed to drawing universal ethical norms from ethical
practices by either inductive or deductive methods: "Within our own
culture, there are standards that we consider peculiarly appropriate for our
own society and standards that we believe all people ought to share. By looking at the universal standards
we come up with and the way in which we draw the distinction between universal
and local standards, we have a model for how to discern similar standards and
similar distinctions in other cultures. And if we can successfully persuade the
authorities and/or members of those cultures that a similar notion of
universality exists within their system, we will have a successful
cross-cultural judgment. What is
important here is that we never go strictly outside either our own or
the other culture: rather, we seek universal principles within both cultures'
traditional terms. We thus
maintain throughout the assumption that the general good cannot be expressed in
a language of its own, but we also maintain, in the very process of trying to
achieve agreement with the other culture, a presupposition that there must be
some notion of ethical rightness transcending all specific ethical
languages." (Fleischacker, The
Ethics of Culture, p. 152.)
Ethics of Distinctive
Particular Activities
As
mentioned above, in recent times much information has been gathered about
ethical beliefs and practices in such fields as health care (including what was
formerly called medical ethics), business, and the professions. The writer will bring forth here some
examples from business ethics, in which it is said that there are some absolute
norms for "morality of the marketplace," such as contract keeping,
prohibition of bribery (countries deny it or officially outlaw it), lying,
theft, fraud ....." (Bowie,
"Business Ethics and Cultural Relativism," in Essentials of
Business Ethics, by Peter Madsen and Jay M. Shafritz, p. 377ff, where Bowie
also assigns a reason, "because without these the market system does not
work," which need not concern us in this section.)
An
example of research into business ethics is a study of business managers who
were asked "initially to discuss moral issues that have arisen in their
daily work and then later analyze these discussions to discern implicit as well
as explicit moral standards to which they refer as they describe these
issues." The most common
moral (ethical) standards invoked by the 193 respondents were (with the percent
of total cases in which the standard was invoked): 1. honesty in communications
(25.9%), 2. fair treatment (30.1%), 3. special consideration (15.0%), 4. fair
competition (29.5%), 5. organizational responsibility (21.2%), 6. social
responsibility (5.7%), 7. respect for law (9.3%). (Bird and Waters, "The nature of Managerial Moral
Standards.")
Another
example: 420 questionnaires (30.7% response rate) from marketing executives and
researchers, 62% male and 38% female, expressing on a Likert scale agreement or
non-agreement with 11 brief dubiously ethical scenarios found the women less
likely than the men to agree with the dubious action. In only two were the mean ratings equal; in six the women
were slightly less condoning, and in three they were notably less so (in these
three instances the mean were male 2.6 - female 2.2, male 2.9 - female 2.5,
male 3.7 - female 3.3. While the
authors do not theorize about the reason for the difference, they propose that
as the proportion of women in these responsble positions increases, so will the
level of ethical standards.
(Akaah, "Differences in Research Ethics Judgments Between Male and
Female Marketing Professionals.")
Developmental Ethics
It
is obvious that children do not come into this world expressing the kind of
ethical judgments which they will be expressing in later life. It is commonly
observed, furthermore, that this is not merely due to the learning of language
adequate for expressing ethical judgments, but it is also due to some
development of the child's capacity to perceive his or her actions in a
framework of right/wrong, good/evil.
Catholic theology, as an example, since the fifteenth century speaks of
an "age of reason" (about seven years), at which time the child
becomes able to tell right from wrong and consequently is responsible for his
or her actions.
Latent
in such theology's approach to developmental ethics is the understanding that
the child learns certain objective, universal principles of ethics and gains
the ability to reason with them.
Simple and attractive as this understanding may be, it contains
presuppositions that have in modern times been tested and found wanting. The psychoanalytic study of the
unconscious and the psychosocial study of group influences have shown that many
factors beyond rational analysis of ethical principles enter into what children
and adults judge to be right and wrong as well as into how they apply
principles to particular cases.
The
temptation to social scientists researching developmental ethics has been to
reduce ethics to a contentless coping mechanism. Even such a classical Freudian psychoanalyst as Robert
Coles, however, came to the conclusion that he could not explain the strength
of character, that is to say the virtue, of some children that way. (Robert Coles, The Moral Life of
Children.)
Jean
Piaget is credited with calling the attention of psychologists to phases in the
evolution of ethical judgment in children. Briefly put, Piaget writes of "... the existence of
three great periods in the development of the sense of justice in the child. One period, lasting up to the age of
7-8, during which justice is subordinated to adult authority; a period
contained approximately between 8-11, and which is that of progressive
equalitarianism; and finally a period which sets in towards 11-12, and during
which purely equalitarian justice is tempered by considerations of
equity." (Piaget, The
Moral Judgment of the Child," p. 314.)
This
line of investigation has been pursued in America by Lawrence Kohlberg, whose
description of three levels of ethical development, each divided into two
stages, is so well known that we will merely allude to it here: In level one,
preconventional morality, stage one, punishment and obedience orientation,
yields to stage 2, instrument and relativity orientation; in the second level,
that of conventional morality, stage 3, interpersonal concordance orientation,
yields to stage 4, law and order orientation; at the highest level,
postconventional or autonomous morality, comes stage 5, social contract
orientation, and stage 6, universal ethical principles orientation. (This structure is laid out in
Kohlberg, Moral Development and Behavior.")
In
later years Kohlberg himself came to assert that he had no empirical evidence
that anyone attains stage 6 of ethical development. He and his colleagues have, nevertheless, convincingly
defended themselves from accusations of sex bias and philosophical bias. (See Kohlberg, Levine, and Hewer, Moral
Stages: A Current Formulation and a Response to Critics, passim.) Whatever controversy there may be about
his work, Kohlberg's line of investigation is clearly important and his
conclusions are at least an approximation of a verifiable description of what
happens to the ethical thinking of people as they grow older, and they provide
us with the useful heuristic concept of arrested ethical development.
Ethics in Literature
Some
literature (read or performed or both) can be used by the ethicist to
illustrate ethical situations and viewpoints. This is particularly true for restricted ethical fields
like, for instance, business ethics or medical ethics. Other literature seems more to present
an ethical world of some kind which the reader or viewer can use to meditate on
ethics. Following are some of my
observations on works of the latter kind.
* Homer, The
Odyssey (read in translation).
Epistemology:
it is set in a mythical era when anything can happen.
Philosophical
anthropology: man is subject to the whims of the gods - yet, he determines his
own actions and is responsible for them.
Ethics:
while misfortune is caused by the gods, evil is in people in the form of greed,
self-conceit, lack of respect (servile piety), stealing, cruelty, etc. (Lying
is scarcely presented as evil.) Patience, magnanimity, filial and servile
piety, and kindness are good. Thus the norm of morality lies not in the consequences,
which are reward and punishment, but in what can be called rectitude or right
ordering of a person's actions.
This concerns ethical action in the abstract - in the concrete, ethical
action takes the form of the virtues and the text could be studied at length
with this in mind.
* Goethe, Faust
Epistemology:
The illusions are of the devil. They produce permanent effects (especially
those performed for the emperor). The experience with Helen is different from
the illusions it is myth
rewritten, and the force behind it is the devil as myth, not as evil.
Cosmology:
Evil is powerful, but limited, and good triumphs in the end. Evil forces are
blind and do not see that they will lose; good forces are confident and
patient.
Philosophy
of man: Faust appears to be an Everyman, who is wise enough to see through the
learned disciplines and foolish enough to hope to accomplish great things by
magic. Still, he never ceases trying, and so he is saved both from the power of
evil and from his own foolishness.
Ethics:
Moral evil seems to arise from misguided attempts at doing good. As such, it is
reparable as long as the striving for good remains.
* Franz Kafka,
The Metamorphosis (Die Verwandlung) (read in translation):
Forward
to philosophical consideration: This seems primarily to be the story of a
person who sacrifices himself for others, becoming nothing rather than
something in the process. For five years Gregor Samsa worked hard to support
his family, but gained almost no love from them and certainly no respect.
Furthermore, they became dependent on him and lost their strength, if not their
self-respect. When he turned into a beetle or roach he showed himself for what
he had become, but, although present, he could no longer act the role. No
longer dependent on him, all three members of his family became able to take
care of themselves and be happy together. When he completely realized that they
did not want him at all and that he was an obstacle to their welfare, he
died. In current terminology an
enabler, Gregor found out that the people dependent on one like him feel
revulsion rather than love toward the enabler and that they are better off
without him. Consistent to the end, Gregor accepted this judgment, his
transformation, and his death.
This is a psychological drama, not a philosophical one. There are, however, philosophical
implications:
Epistemology:
Gregor knew that he was repulsive, but he did not grasp the tragic
contradiction involved in looking like a beetle but thinking like a man. The events are dreamlike, nightmarish.
Philosophy
of man: man's unique position among beings on earth is not secure if his allout
efforts can reduce him to animal stature.
The story can be taken as an allegory, a modern myth, and seen this way
it makes no difference if Gregor turned into a beetle or thought he did.
Whether or not he turned into a beetle does not affect the points which the
story makes.
* Edgar Lee
Masters, Spoon River Anthology
performed by the Boulevard Players of Milwaukee.
Philosophy
of man: This selection of about one-third of the soliliquies with songs, mainly
hymns of rural Protestant America, seems to convey most of all a sense of vital
force which diffuses itself into the interrelated lives of the people who had
lived in the town, runs its course, and then rests.
Ethics:
Although much is said about the morals of the townsfolk, the work neither
moralizes nor judges: the vital force is not to be captured by categories of
good or bad. Each life, while
small, is not senseless or meaningless.
The worth of the vital force is expressed in terms of religion, but it
is not necessary to suppose that the author is maintaining that the expression
of a higher order is anything but the form of expression which these people
find available.
PARTICULAR ETHICAL
NORMS
In
reviewing the list of well known ethical norms it seems easiest to begin with
the ones which derive from good results.
The simple reason for this is that results are observable. Thus, in rapid review:
HEDONISM
judges actions to be good to the extent that they procure pleasure for the
individual. This agrees roughly
with our notion of leading to organic unity, although, since it involves
emotion, it also includes some intentional unity.
EUDAEMONISM
judges actions to be good to the extent that they procure the individual's
happiness. This compares
substantially with our notion of leading to intentional unity. Eudaemonism is sometimes taken to be a
spiritualized version of Hedonism.
An historical note about eudaemonism. Plato's ethics are eudaemonistic:
happiness is man's highest good.
The pursuit of virtue brings happiness. Plato seconds Socrates in holding that actions are bad out
of ignorance. (Frederick
Copleston, A History of Philosophy, vol 1, pp 216-22.) Note, however, that the
connection between happiness as contemplation of forms and everyday action is
very loose. Iris Murdoch points
out the discourse of Diotima in the Symposium: good is what all men seek, and
it is related intrinsically to beauty and love. (Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals, p. 343.)
ALTRUISM
judges actions to be good if they bring about the pleasure or happiness of
others. It is based on the
similarity between self and others, and it can, but does not have to, be taken
in the sense of society versus the individual.
RESPECT
sees as good those actions which grant to others benefits which are due to them
because of their standing in society.
Claims to respect are not based on particular actions the way personal
justice is; on the other hand they may establish differences which affect the
application of fairness. A
particular form of respect is respect for rights, that is, claims to respect
which arise from societyÕs action of constituting itself politically or
economically. Rights are defined
and defended by law, but aside from their legal nature they have ethical
aspects. Such ethical aspects are
brought out by the notion of "Human Rights," which are taken to be
claims to respect that can be made by all human citizens of the world. It is clear that the notion of
"claim to respect" can extend to trivial actions such as mere
courtesy. We can avoid a long
investigation into this matter by accepting generally accepted human rights as
ethically significal claims to respect.
A
comprehensive working, but not non-controversial, list of rights is that of the
United NationsÕ 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Articles 1
to 21, such as the rights to life, liberty, security of person, ownership of
property, and freedom of opinion and expression, came from the non-Communist bloc and are generally
civil-political. Articles 22 to
29, such as the rights to work, to rest and leisure, to food, clothing and
housing, and to education on the
other hand, were proposed by the Communist bloc and are generally
social-economic. The latter set of
rights seems to relate more to the goals of society than to the relationships
between the people who compose it.
However this may be, some of the listed rights seem more basic than
others and some are more easilty legislated than others. (The text of the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights and these comments on it are from Maurice
Cranston, What are Human Rights?)
It
is difficult to make a satisfactory list of basic human rights. Jack Donnelly thinks that Henry ShueÕs
list of three -- subsistence, security, and liberty -- is the best, but that
even it is questionable. (Jack
Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice. He cites Henry
ShueÕs Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy.)
Greeks
and Romans held the state (city, empire) to be supreme, all-powerful, having
been founded and constituted on a religious basis -- no individual could
question it or stand up to it.
(Numa Denis Fustel de Coulanges, The Ancient City, Book 3,
Chapter 17.)
Notably
early among Europeans to have a notion of civil-political rights were the
English. The Magna Charta
in 1215 is the best known historical document in the English development of the
notion of rights, but it is neither the beginning nor the end of that
development. (Geoffrey Hindley, The
Book of Magna Carta.)
Although
pressure for social-economic rights was not a notable feature of the
development of rights until the socialist movements of the nineteenth century,
the American Thomas Paine, in defending the French Revolution from the
criticisms of Edmund Burke, maintains that such benefits as universal
education, maternity benefits, and family allowances for the poor should be
considered rights. (Thomas Paine, The
Rights of Man, Part II.)
Another
historical aspect of the development of the notion of rights in Europe:
"When the Spaniards struck at the city-building empires of Mexico and Peru
they saw them as weaker versions of the empires of Alexander and Augustus,
problematic enough in logistic and diplomatic terms, but, because of this
analogy, not a radical challenge to rethinking the nature of political
societies. Those ancient empires
had been overcome. So, now, had
these. It was the greater number
of apparently more primitive peoples in central and southern America that
aroused a crisis of conscience, public debate, and an element of
self-scrutiny. Missionaries'
consciences were initially troubled by two questions. The first was: do people living in a state of nature have property
rights: If they do, do we
have the right to dispossess and enslave them? The second was: do these people, who seem to live the
instinctive lives of animals, have souls?
If they do, should we not convert and protect rather than exploit
them? This, the first pertinent
and passionate discussion of abstract human rights, went on for a generation
and more between settlers' needs for labour and priests' concern for potential
converts. It was at last resolved
in the mid-century in favour of the view that the Amerindian masses were, like
their better-armed and more singleminded masters, men with legal rights and
souls to save." (John Hale, The
Civilization of Europe in the Renaissance, p. 46.)
On
the one hand the extension of notions of rights beyond their European and
American origins seems to be an ethical action for the welfare of the people of
other cultures. On the other hand,
however, the manner in which they are extended is taken to be cultural imperialism,
an imposition of distinctive Western values on peoples who have values of their
own. It seems to me that this
controversy is totally avoidable if we look at rights as I have above: that is,
as societal forms of respect. It
is, nevertheless, a real conflict, as is evidenced by the article ÒÕAsian
ValuesÕ and Global RightsÓ by Fred Dallmayr. My chapters on Indian and Chinese ethics also touch on this
subject.
Stephen
Holmes & Cass Sunstein, The Cost of Rights, New
York: Norton, 1999, although dealing strictly with legal rights, presents interesting
aspects which are often overlooked:
Limiting
themselves to legal rights, which they carefully distinguish from moral rights,
the authors argue against what they assert to be the current understanding of
the distinction between negative and positive rights (see quote below from page
51), and they argue that all legal rights require society's financial resources
to maintain, and that this is a price a society pays for securing the
cooperation of its members in pursuing its common goals.
"Personal
liberty, as Americans value and experience it, presupposes social cooperation
managed by government officials.
Thr private realm we rightly prize is sustained, indeed created, by
public action. Not even the most
self-reliant citizen is asked to look after his or her material welfare
autonomously, without any support from fellow citizens or public
officials." p. 15.
Definition
of rights: "important interests that can be reliably protected by
individuals or groups using the instrumentalities of government." Then the
distinction between moral and legal rights. p. 16.
A
long list of rights -the authors want it to be confusing, and it contains legal
relationships which are not necessarily rights at all. p. 37-39.
The
authors present a caricature of the implications of the distinction of rights
into positive and negative, making it to be a polarity of rugged individualism
vs welfare mentality, and they assert that this is the accepted way of
thinking. p. 39-43.
"Rights
are costly because remedies are costly.
Enforcement is expensive, especially uniform and fair enforcement; and
legal rights are hollow to the extent that they remain unenforced. Formulated differently, almost every
right implies a correlative duty, and duties are taken seriously only when
dereliction is punished by the public power drawing on the public
purse." In the immediately
preceding paragraph, however, is the assertion, "'Where there is a right,
there is a remedy' is a classical legal maxim.... What it shows is that all
legally enforced rights are necessarily positive rights." p. 43.
On
positive and negative rights again:
"The wholly reasonable distinction between forbearance and
performance lends no credence to the opposition between immunity against
government interference and entitlement to government service." p. 51
"Those
who describe rights as absolutes make it impossible to ask an important factual
question: Who decides at what level to
fund which cluster of basic rights for whom? How fair, as well as how prudent, is our current system of
allocating scarce resources among competing rights, including constitutional
rights? And who exactly is
empowered to make such allocative decisions?" page 131.
"When
efforts at moral persuasion fail, rights are likely to be asserted instead. Arguments 'against rights,' therefore,
may make more sense if reinterpreted as complaints about inadequate social
norms and our need to respond to their defects. The right to be free from certain kinds of pollution
("nonsmokers' rights') and the right to be free from racial hate speech (a
right vindicated by many campus speech codes) are regularly advanced when
social norms falter. And once such
rights are legally recognized, the costs to the taxpayer may be high .p. 169.
"Conceived
as a matter of public finance, legal rights emerge as politically created and
collectively funded instruments designed to promote human welfare. Because returns from equal rights
protection - such as the benefit of living in a relatively just society where,
for the most part, groups with different ethnic backgrounds can peaceably
coexist and cooperate - are diffuse and hard to capture, initial investments in
such protection must be made by the public power." p. 221.
Rights
can be situated within the broader range of ethical action as responsiveness to
value. (Robert Nozick, Philosophical
Explanations, 498-504, where responsiveness to value seems to equal
respect.)
PERSONAL
JUSTICE calls an action good if the action preserves or restores equality in an
exchange of benefits between individuals.
That the individuals are fundamentally on a par with each other is
understood here, too.
FAIRNESS
as a common and non-technical notion declares that an action is good if it
treats a plurality of individuals in the same way, or, to put it another way,
the action is good if it applies the same rule to all who are affected by
it. It explicitly and emphatically
derives from the similarity between individuals in a group and, by extension,
to the individuals in society at large.
It is necessary, however, that there be a reason for applying fairness
as an ethical norm, as there is, for instance, in game playing or in the
relationships between businesses.
Another fairness situation is that of the distribution of benefits, and
this is called distributive justice.
Although
the notion of distributive justice is quite simple, great problems arise in the
application of it because there are often many and varied rules which could be
used. Thoroughly egalitarian distributive justice is, perhaps, the easiest to
use, but, being rather simplistic, it ignores the consideration that mere equal
distribution may be far from equal is its effects on varied recipients. Socialist distributive justice, on the
other hand, expressed in the classical dictum, from each according to his
abilities, to each according to his needs, implies a political philosophy
which is by no means universally accepted. The modern attempt of John Rawls to include opportunity
in the rule of distribution at least indicates the multiplicity of factors that
can be taken into account
John
Rawls insists on the modern role of the state as a source of entitlements
(social-economic benefits), as socialism does, but it leaves intact the
capitalistic potential for gain by some, while ensuring the civil rights of
all. And this is with a minimum of
commitment to any political system.
Note the historical relationships: this notion was scarcely possible
before World War II because not enough attention had been paid before that
toward reconciling capitalism and socialism. RawlsÕs principle is stated: 1) each person has an equal right to the most extensive
basic liberties compatible with similar liberties for all, 2) social and
economic inequities are arranged so that they are both a) to the greatest benefit of the least
advantaged persons, b) attached to offices and positions open to all under
conditions of fair equality of opportunity. The principle works in this way: if all people were equally
talented they would be treated equally, but since they are not, social,
political, and economic institutions are arranged to favor those who would
suffer from inequality.
Illustrations are the graduated income tax, selective sales tax, divorce
settlements protecting non-earners, and, specifically about oppportunity: it is
promoted in favor of those who might not (or do not) have it: job
opportunities, educational opportunities, opportunities to be in politics, and
the like. (A Theory of Justice,
1971.)
UTILITARIANISM
pronounces an action good if it has social effects and produces a greater sum
total of pleasure or happiness than any other action under the same
circumstances
Utilitarianism
was the title of John Stuart MillÕs 1863 essay which popularized this
norm. Mill wrote of the Greatest
Happiness Principle, which Òholds that actions are right in proportion as
they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of
happiness. By happiness is
intended pleasure and the absence of pain
-- by unhappiness, pain and
the privation of pleasure.Ó And Òthat
standard is not the agentÕs own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of
happiness altogether.Ó Mill was
concerned with both the quantity and the quality of happiness. Thus he asserted that feeding hungry people
might be enough to make them happy, but if they were once fed, merely keeping
them fed would not be sufficient to keep them happy. Love, knowledge, wisdom, and the like would be needed for
this. Knowledge, says Mill, is
better than fashionable clothing, peace of mind is better than a full stomach,
appreciation of art is better than sex.
ÒIt is better to be a man dissatisfied than a pig satisfied, better to
be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.Ó Mill saw two arguments for including others in the happiness
calculation: 1) the Òsocial
feelings of mankind -- the desire to be in unity with our fellow-creatures,Ó
and 2) all have an equal claim to happiness. According to him social inequalities, such as the
suppression of women, should disappear.
Furthermore, Utility, as he intended it, is very democratic: one person
is as valuable as another. (John
Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism.)
Volumes have been written about Utilitarianism, but the writer of the
present essay is not convinced that much substance has been added to MillÕs
short work on it.
An
historical note on the development of the utilitarian point of view in American
Business: "The
anti-intellectualism of businessmen, interpreted narrowly as hostility to
intellectuals, is mainly a political phenomenon. But interpreted more broadly as a suspicion of intellect
itself, it is part of the extensive American devotion to practicality and
direct experience which ramifies through almost every area of American
life. With some variations of details
suitable to social classes and historical circumstances, the excessive
practical bias so often attributed only to business is found almost everywhere
in America. In itself, a certain wholesome regard for the practical needs no
defense and deserves no disparagement so long as it does not aspire to
exclusiveness, so long as other aspects of human experience are not denigrated
and ridiculed. Practical vigor is
a virtue; what has been spiritually crippling in our history is the tendency to
make a mystique of practicality."
(Richard Hofstadter, Anti-intellectualism in American Life, pp.
236-237.)
Again,
"The more thoroughly business dominated American society, the less it felt
the need to justify its existence by reference to values outside its own
domain. In earlier days it had
looked for sanction in the claim that the vigorous pursuit of trade served God,
and later that it served character and culture. Although this argument did not disappear, it grew less
conspicuous in the business rationale.
As business became the dominant motif in American life and as a vast
material empire rose in the New World, business increasingly looked for
legimation in a purely material and internal criterion -- the wealth it produced. American business, once defended on the
ground that it produced a high standard of culture, was now defended mainly on
the ground that it produced a high standard of living. Few businessmen would have hesitated to
say that the advancement of material prosperity, if not itself a kind of moral ideal,
was at least the presupposition of all other moral ideals." (Hofstadter, 251-252.)
The
evident importance and reasonableness of the consequential norms as a whole
could deceive one into thinking that no more need be said about ethical norms
in general. We know, however, that
we must also look at the initial state from which ethical actions proceed, and
when we do this we find another set of ethical norms. Again in rapid review:
DEONTOLOGISM
holds that an action must proceed from a good intention if it is to be
good. This is conceived of as pure
ethical motivation as distinguished from pragmatic motivation: according to
deontologism whether or not the action actually achieves something it is good
at least to the extent that it starts out good.
A
question for deontologism is, ÒHow can I be sure that my intention is good?Ó No one has ever shown to the general
satisfaction of ethicists that we have a special ethical sense that would
assure us of this without regard to consequences. Moreover, as the writer has already noted, ethicists do not
claim that pure feeling or emotion is an adequate ethical guide, and if we have
a personal daimon, or
imperious inner voice telling us what we should do, then no one else can check
it for us except by external evaluation.
The most famous attempt to turn good intention into an applicable norm,
KantÕs Categorical Imperative, involves a thought process rather than a direct
intuition, and if anyone has improved on Kant in this regard the formula used
has certainly not gained general acceptance.
VIRTUE
ETHICS holds that the action of a good person is, unless vitiated, a good
one. In other words, that a good
person tends primarily to put its goodness into action. This goodness, however, is not
abstract: it has to do with the relationships which the good person has with
self, others, and the world. These
relationships, the virtues, are definable, and they involve typical actions,
which are recognized to be virtuous.
The
question which arises from viewing people as possessors of virtue is, "How
does a good person act?" A
list of virtues with the reasons why they express goodness will answer the
question. Aristotle's classic list
of moral virtues has been followed by many others. The virtues which Aristotle treats in books three to five
of The Nicomachean Ethics
are courage, temperance ("Sophrosyne"), liberality, magnificence,
justifiable pride, proper ambition, restraint of anger, restraint of
boastfulness, and justice, although he notes at the beginning of book six that
there are still other moral virtues.
A
recent grouping of virtues which the writer finds useful in particular
applications of ethics is that of James Wallace. According to him there are three groups of virtues. The virtues of the first group include
courage, even-temperedness, patience, and something which has been called
temperance or self-control. These
virtues have the function of forestalling the disruptions and interferences
which desires and aversions of various kinds create for practical reasoning and
its appropriate actions. Wallace
does not give these virtues a generic name, but for the sake of using them
practically in ethical analysis we shall, with apology to him, give them the
group appellation of self-control.
(James D. Wallace, Virtues and Vices, p. 60ff.)
The
second group of virtues Wallace calls conscientiousness, and it includes
honesty, fairness, truthfulness, and being a person of one's word. Here we also
find, he writes, Kant's duty.
(Wallace, p. 90ff.)
Benevolence
is Wallace's third set of virtues.
Included under it are kindness, generosity, humaneness, and
compassion. Nothing, of course,
prevents one action from representing both conscientiousness and benevolence,
he asserts. (Wallace, p. 128ff.)
Another
list of virtues is, "Six moral principles may be formulated which state
the ideals involved in these levels of perfection: prudence (acting for one's
own highest good), loyalty (fulfilling specific obligations to other
individuals or groups), benevolence (promoting the general welfare), justice
(ordering society fairly and equitably), agape (acting with unselfish
devotion to the needs of anyone), and universal piety (furthering the
perfections of being at any level)." (Donald Walhout, The Good and the
Realm of Values, p. 85.)
Instead
of elaborating a list of virtues one might propose that one certain virtue is
the essential attribute of a good person.
It seems to the writer that this is risky and is liable to lead to a
more subjective view than a philosopher would wish. For instance, if one follows Agnes Heller's definition of
the good person, the minimum attribute needed for being called good, "A
person is good if he or she prefers to suffer wrong than to wrong others,"
one will probably be led also to agree with her that there is no rational proof
of this, that it is a "confession of faith" grounded in the
observation that good persons do exist with what she also calls a basic
"honesty" that provides the way of the supererogatory goodness of the
saint or the altruist or the "genius of morality." (General Ethics, pp. 174-176.)
The
thinking behind the notion of virtue is so different from the thinking behind
some other commonly used norms that is is very difficult to compare it with
them. For an example of an exercise in doing this see Michael Slote's From
Morality to Virtue. The book has the title that it does because for him
"morality" has to do with right and wrong, which are concerns of
Kantianism, Utilitarianism, and "Common Sense Ethics," whereas virtue
has to do with good and bad. Slote
assumes that we know about virtue and the virtues and does not explain
them. The virtues he mentions by
name are: (other-regarding) justice, kindness, probity, generosity;
(self-regarding) prudence, sagacity, circumspection, equanimity, fortitude;
(either) self-control, courage, practical wisdom, moderation.
INNER
LAW ETHICS contends that there are in human beings inbuilt patterns of action
which should be followed. This is
sometimes expressed in terms of a human nature, with which we should act in
harmony. It is also said to be the
observance of the natural law in ourselves.
DIVINE
LAW ETHICS holds that actions are good or evil to the extent that they are in
conformity to a rule divinely established in us. According to some schools of thought this coincides with
inner law ethics, and according to others it does not coincide with it because
God can be arbitrary in what he demands of us.
An
historical note about divine law ethics in the U.S: one of the roots of American anti-intellectualism is the
kind of religion that grew with it. Detached from the churches of Europe at
first, it, except for Puritan practice, had active disdain for the history and
dogma of Europe and for reasoned attempts to reconcile religious faith with human
understanding. Revivalism and
fundamentalism thus became marked traits of American religion. with here and
there, now and then, religious intellectuals being critical and championing
universities as forums for exchange of thought. (Hofstadter, Part II: The Religion of the Heart, pages
55-141.)
We
have so far two camps of ethical norms, and it remains to be seen how the two
relate to each other. There are,
however, still other norms which are not based on either terminus of the
ethical action, but which regard the whole of the action. As will be evident, these norms are
complex and greatly overlap the norms previously noted, but they are in some
ways different from the rest.
Briefly:
PERFECTIONISM
judges an action to be good if enhances the being of the actor, whether this is
an individual or society, whether the enhancement consists in having a good
intention or in bringing about good results. This might seem too general to be a norm, and it certainly
partially coincides with several of the other norms; nevertheless it states
something different from any of them.
Some
elucidation of perfectionism.
"Perfectionism generally requires each person to act so as to
realize fully her essential capacities and sees the main goal of the state to
be the improvement of its citizens, where this is understood to involve the
development and exercise of their essential capacities and powers." (p.11)
Perfectionists include Plato, Aristotle, Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Mill, Bradley,
Green, and Hobhouse. Objections to
perfectionism include the difficulty of determining what is perfection for the
individual and of reconciling perfections to produce the most perfect State
(like summing happinesses). Some
reference to equality among persons needs to be built into perfectionist
ethical theory. These are the
thoughts of the author, and the reviewer adds his own view that Aristotle's
notion of friendship, mutually perfective love, can be extended to answer the
question about general perfection because it means that self-perfection is an
ethical concept, whereas, as the author says, it is not necessarily
ethical. (David O. Brink,
"Pursuing perfections," Times Literary Supplement, June 24,
1994, pp.11-12, a review of Thomas Hurka, Perfectionism, Oxford
University Press, 1993.)
A
somewhat different meaning of perfectionism is presented by Edmund Pincoffs:
"I will take it that moral perfectionism, in its most general form, as it
bears on actions and policies, is the doctrine that the overall acceptability
or unacceptability of an action or policy is to be determined by the extent to
which the action or policy accords with standards of excellence." For Pincoffs the virtues are among such
standards. (Pincoffs, Quandaries
and Virtues, p. 104.)
VALUE
ETHICS is based on the relationship which people have with things through conscious
interest in them. People evaluate
states, whether initial or final, according to some norm; they act upon what
they perceive to be values. Values
closely resemble goods - whatever is a good is a value and vice versa - but,
rather than being connected with any metaphysical system, they are connected
with the psychological process (evaluation) by which people relate to a world
which consists not just of facts in themselves but of facts which interest
them. The norms of ethical
evaluation are practically speaking indistinguishable from the norms of ethics
already presented in this essay, but they are approached through psychology
rather than through ontology.
Value ethics is congenial to the modern pragmatic, non-metaphysical
American mind, but the writer refers back to his contention that metaphysics
cannot be avoided. Still, as long
as their respective backgrounds are kept in mind, ethicists of values and
ethicists of good should have no difficulty in conversing about norms and other
aspects of ethics.
Philosophers
who discourse about values tend to range them in hierarchies such as those of
the Phenomenologist Max Scheler: sensible feeling, such as the occasions of
agreeable and disagreeable sensations - vital feeling, such as the source of
emotions - spiritual, such as knowledge, beauty, and rectitude - religious,
such as the holy. (Max Scheler, Formalism
in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values, pp. 105-110.) Similar in application is the needs
hierarchy of Abraham Maslow:
physiological - safety - love & belonging - esteem & self-esteem
- self-actualization. (Maslow, Motivation
and Personality.)
A
useful, extensive scheme of values is the following "outline of human
values" of Donald Walhout (Donald Walhout, The Good and the Realm of
Values.):
I. Metavalues
A. Protovalues
1. Life itwelf
2. Maturation and growth
3. Mental Health
4. World peace
B. Supravalues
1. Freedom
2. Creativity
3. Religion
C. Epivalue: harmonious
perfecting
II.
Principal Values
A. Values of reverence, or
theocentric values
1. Experience of the holy
2. Experience of accord
B. Values of appreciation, or natural
values
1. Psychophysical states
a)
Pleasure - bodily and mental
b)
Skill - bodily and mental
2. Natural piety
3. Esthetic experience
4. Cosmic awe
C. Values of human
relatedness, or moral values
1. Individuality
2. Family life, including sexual love
3. Friendship and association
4. Active citizenship
5. Moral character
D. Values of knowledge, or
intellectual values
1. Knowing
2. Inquiring
Although
Walhout would appeal to nuances of difference, his fundamental position is a
Thomist one, that good is a transcendental and that evil is the lack of
good. He develops the thesis that
values are defined as goods that are reached by conscious and free
actions. Goods outside human
conscious life are values because they are consciously apprehended as such by
God. He avoids saying that this is
a metaphysical concept of value.
He places himself among self-teleological eudaemonists, but he avoids
saying that right action is that which brings about self-perfection: right action
is virtuous action, which takes others into account. He also has a deontological side, which paraphrases the
Categorical Imperative.
An
historical note about general value theory in the U.S.: It arose early in the 20th century as a
way of expressing a general human ability to have conscious interest as opposed
to making judgments of pure fact.
Of course it involves no metaphysics, and it avoids the use of terms
like good and bad, although it brings in the notion of norm. Contemporary American philosophers are backing away from the
deep dichotomy of fact versus value, and they have made some progress in
studying particular kinds of values and then generalizing as opposed to the
original general, deductive approach.
(Abraham Edel, "The Concept of Value and Its Travels in
Twentieth-Century America,"
pp. 12-36 in Values and Value Theory in Twentieth-Century America,
Murphey and Berg.)
An
historical note about John Dewey he
is not a value philosopher, but he writes about value. Thus, "Something is a value if it
is adapted 'to the needs and demands imposed by the situation'. that is to say,
if it meets the demands of an objective problematic situation, in regard to its
transformation or reconstruction.
A judgment of value, like a scientific hypothesis, is predictive, and it
is thus empirically or experimentally verifiable.'" I.e., value is neither a reality in
itself nor purely subjective.
(Quoted in Copleston, A History of Philosophy, vol VIII, p. 371.)
An
historical note about semantic problems regarding American usage of
"value:" "In a sample
study of texts in the late 1950s, I found that the situation [the
indeterminateness of the term 'value'] was complicated by the use of another
concept alongside, that of norms.
In philosophic usage, the latter suggested the normative, the
judgmental; the evaluation of one's own or another's values is a normative
enterprise. But in the usage of
psychological or social science it appeared that the norms were rather the ways
of acting that took shape as rules; hence the norms of a society or culture were
the rules that operated in socialization of the growing child or in efforts to
control the conduct of people.
Thus although the rules were normative (in the philosophical sense) the
enterprise of presenting the norms of a given society or culture was avowedly
descriptive. On the other hand,
'value' was often defined, in a judgmental reference, as the criteria employed
for evaluation of conduct or decision or for justifying the norms. The concepts of norm and value thus
turned out to have an inverse relation: where a scientist used 'norms'
descriptively, 'value' tended to be used judgmentally for criteria of
evaluation; but where 'value' was used descriptively, 'norm' tended to be used
judgmentally." (Abraham Edel,
"The Concept of Value and Its Travels in Twentieth-Century America in
Murray G. Murphey and Ivar Berg, Values and Value Theory in
Twentieth-Century America, p. 27.)
A
note about Max Scheler: his phenomenological descriptions of the intentionality
of value orientation are probably unsurpassed. He is one with American value theorists in asserting that
values, including ethical ones, are not founded on metaphysics, but his method
also leads him to avoid a scientific (psychological) empirical approach to
values. Furthermore, although he
expresses himself in such a way as to make it appear that we have a special
sense of values or, which is the same, that values constitute a separate order
of reality, this is really an effect of his phenomenological method, which
blanks out the perceptions and realities which are not directly involved in the
intentional relationship under consideration. (Scheler, Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of
Values.)
To
do justice to SchelerÕs value analysis one needs to know the five
characteristics of ÒheightÓ which serve to rank them in their hierarchy. Then, however, to do justice to
SchelerÕs limitations, one needs to know the criticism of him made by Nicolai
Hartmann, who adds a principle of ranking by ÒstrengthÓ or Òweight.Ó At least one other phenomenologist,
Hans Reiner, has combined these principles and added others, making a total of
eleven. (Alfons Deeken, Process
& Permanence in Ethics: Mac SchelerÕs Moral Philosophy, New York:
Paulist Press, 1974, pp. 44-61, ÒThe Hierarchy of Values and the Laws of Value-Preference.Ó)
Historical
notes about modern French value philosophy: it takes several shapes: Raymond
Polin was a phenomologist who rejected a metaphysical interpretation of
value; RenŽ Le Senne, in a
philosophy of spirit, described value as "That which is worthy of being
sought after", and this is objective, the absolute, God, being the pure
and infinite value; Raymond Ruyer is similar to Le Senne, quite theistic; Jean
Pucelle connects his value theory with the Judeo-Christian tradition, but bases
it on being, saying that "... it is because value is a relation between
Being and beings that every existence has value." (Copleston, vol. 9, pp. 294-307.) Camus's literature of the absurd
includes values: by choosing to live "he asserts a value, that life is
good or worth living or should be made worth living" (397). "The man of the absurd... exhibits
the greatness of man precisely by this combination of recognition of ultimate
futility with a life of self-sacrificing love" (393). (Copleston, vol. 9, pp. 393-397.)
The
ethics of Existentialist thinkers such as Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus
fall under the norm of value in the present essay. The reason is that Existentialism has no referents for good
and evil except the development of the acting individual, who ÒcreatesÓ
himself, that is to say, who produces his own essence. The individual achieves a value, or,
rather, becomes a value. Thus,
although Existentialists have their own vocabulary for describing ethical
action, commentators on Existentialism can best describe it by using the
vocabulary of values.
COMMON
WILL ETHICS takes society, rather than the individual, to be the starting point
of ethical action. It supposes
that where there is a common will, this originates in the union of the members,
which is a good state. This union
can be thought of as merely intentional or as being a more mystical oneness.
Synthesis of ethical norms
We
have named and briefly described 14 ethical norms, and this rather well covers
the range of them. There are
various schemes for grouping these norms, but the one we have used brings out
first of all their relation to good action.
One
can, and many do, look upon the ethical norms as competing among
themselves. Thus, if you are a
Utilitarian you cannot be a Deontologist, but, even so, Utilitarians know that
good intention means something and Deontologists know that a greater sum total
of good has its merits. I submit
that viewing the norms from the perspective of metaphysics as I have done in my
chapter on philosophical elements in general ethics does justice to all of them
while it also points out their limitations. I do not hesitate to assert that each of the norms is
correct in its own way because each expresses a unifying action. An action which verifies any of the
norms is, to that extent, an ethically good action. Clearly, an action which is not good by any of the norms is
not a good action. Conversely, an
action which fails against any of the norms is, to that extent, ethically
bad. In spite of the fact that it
may be a good action according to some norm, it is defective in its unifying
force. In other words, an
action is ethically good if it is good according to at least one ethical norm
and is not bad according to any other ethical norm.
One
consequence of this way of viewing ethical actions and norms is that is
prevents one from drawing an absolute ethical line, to one side of which are
good actions and to the other side of which are bad ones. The ethical evaluation of many actions
is not that simple: many aspects of them have to be considered before a
defensible judgment about their ethicalness can be made. This conclusion is by no means ethical
relativism, which holds that there are no ethical norms inherent in human
actions; neither, however, is it ethical absolutism, which says that there is a
clear-cut right and wrong in all ethical situations.
PROCESS OF ETHICAL
EVALUATION AND DECISION MAKING
Once
we have a firm grasp of the elements of ethics, we find ourselves at the point
where we can make the leap from general principles to the judgment of ethical
action in concrete, particular cases.
We do this by ascertaining which ethical norms apply, a process which
can be called moral
reasoning. We can describe the
basic steps of such reasoning in the terms of Aristotelian logic, that is, as a
syllogism in which the major is a statement of an ethical norm and the minor is
a statement of the facts of the case.
The process, however, is not a neatly wrapped, simplistic one, because
it must pay attention both to all the applicable norms and to all the relevant
facts. It is further complicated
if the norms produce an ethical dilemma, in which none of the concrete
alternative actions appears to be good.
Before
we can proceed we must distinguish ethical evaluation and ethical decision
making. The application of the
norms is ethical evaluation, and it can take place at any time before,
during, or after an action. We can
apply the norms to our own individual actions, to the individual actions of
others, or to collective actions.
Sometimes closeness to the situation is best for knowing which norms
apply and sometimes distance from it is best. Ethical decision making, however, is the evaluation made
before the action, the evaluation which one will use for the ethical
action. Ethical decision making is
in the first person, whereas ethical evaluation can be in the first, second or
third person. An ethicist who is
taken seriously will be called upon both to help in decision making and to give
insight into historical analysis.
Evident though this distinction may seem elementary, it needs to be
brought to the fore because it represents two rather diverse goals of the study
of ethics.
Selection of appropriate norms
To
select applicable norms one can look first at useful generalities. Thus social situations call for social
norms such as utility, justice, and fairness, whereas actions which do not
involve other persons can be judged according to the outcome of individual
pleasure or happiness. All
consequentialist ethics have a need for quantification, and the less concrete
the results are or the less immediate, the harder it is to compare them, and
the less useful is the consequentialist norm. On the other hand, as we have already noted, it is difficult
to judge the good intentions of others, and it may be unclear what to expect
from virtue. Along a different
line, actions the outcomes of which are of little or no importance can be
ethical or not solely because of the intention of the person who acts.
Another
generality is that in the usual situation there are both antecedent and
consequent aspects to an action; they are codependent; both are ethically
important. A hidden aspect of
consequentialist norms is that the person who acts ethically according to them
is, on the whole, intending to bring about good, and a hidden aspect of
deontological and similar norms is that the good intention or virtue possessed
tends to bring about good results, and these latter are not a strictly internal
affair of the acting person.
Turning
our attention to the 14 specific norms (of the chapter, Particular Ethical
Norms), we can see that each of the consequentialist norms, hedonism,
eudaemonism, altruism, fairness, respect, and justice, refers to a specific set
of people. The task, then in
applying these norms is to make sure that all the persons affected by an action
are covered and none are left out.
Of all the principles of application that are being mentioned in this
section, this one, simple as it is, is the most powerful and the most needed in
public debate on ethics.
Thus
utilitarianism is applicable for a totality of persons, but this does not do
away with individuals' claim to respect and certain persons' claim to justice,
and it does not diminish the force of arguments of fairness due to the basic
likeness of people. Accepting
one's self as a person among others, one's own pleasure or happiness is as
important as that of others, but the altruistic contrary of this, that the
pleasure or happiness of others is as important as that of one's self is also a
valid norm. We shall trim the
number of consequentialist norms we use by considering healthy hedonism, which
looks at the long run as well as the short, to be one norm with eudaemonism.
Deontologism
is suitable where we have reliable information about the intention of the
acting person. Thus it is most
helpful when judging one's own actions.
This does not mean that we are completely incapable of judging the
intention of others; it means that we must exercise extreme caution in doing so
lest we ourselves run afoul of the consequentialist norm of respect as well as
the deontological norm which applies to our own action of judging. Our own act of judging according to
ethical norms is, of course, an act in itself susceptible of ethical judgment.
Virtue
is neatly applicable as a norm where there is a recognizable pattern of action
which has been, so to speak, preapproved as good. It has been called a disposition to do something rather than
an intention to do it. Thus it
will be more useful in typical cases than it will be in unusual ones.
The
norms of inner law or divine law relate to intention: the intention to be true
to one's nature or to the will of God.
They are going to be applied by those who hold that there is a clearly
defined human nature with correspondingly clearly defined appropriate ways of
acting or that there are clear mandates of God about human action. Other persons making ethical judgments
will not necessarily assent to these purported laws, with the result that
irresolvable conflict can ensue.
Absolute insistence on inner or divine law preempts ethical discourse
with people who have any other approach to ethics, and for this reason we shall
not use it in this essay. We shall look at conflict resolution in ethical
judgments a little farther along, but the matter at hand already announces that
such resolution is not always possible.
Perfectionism
- unlike virtue, which looks at the antecedent of the ethical action - looks at
both the antecedent and the consequent.
It involves any of the norms which apply to the source of the action
along with eudaemonism: the termini of the ethical action reinforce each other. Although this is a felicitous concept,
its application can be divided into its components for analysis, and we shall
analyze according to the components and not need perfectionism as a norm.
As
we have already noted in the chapter on the norms, the ethics of value is
operationally very similar to the ethics of good. Since I, however, have developed my study of ethics out of a
metaphysical framework of good, I will not analyze actions according to values,
although in practice it would be easy for me to dialog about practical ethics
judgments with those who do. In my
chapters on ethics I have no reason to be guilty of saying "value"
where I mean "good," but in applied ethics outside of ethical
treatises it is difficult to avoid the word "value" when
"good" is meant.
The
last of the 14 norms is "common will ethics." This refers not to individual action,
but to the common action of a plurality of people. It is not a norm to apply to individuals at all, and refers
only to collective ethical action.
To
summarize, the norms I propose for use in ethical decision making are:
Consequential eudaemonism
altruism
respect
fairness
justice
utilitarianism
Deontologism
Virtue self-control
conscientiousness
benevolence
The
fundamental procedure for ethical decision making is, as was stated above, to
apply to the situation all the norms which are appropriate. If even one norm is violated the action
is not good, and it is not to be done.
Pursuing the possible forms this situation can take, we can see that
sometimes there is a question of which action is best among good actions. This translates into the ethical
question, is it good to perform a good action when it is possible to do better? As far as I know, none of the
consequentialist norms (including utilitarianism, which contains an external
resemblance to this line of thinking) furnishes an answer to this
question. The norm of virtue has been applied in a mode of
absolute perfectionism with the outcome that the perfect person always would do
the better thing, but this topic arises, not in a philosophical framework, but
in a religious one, in which such a way of acting is thought to be more
godlike. We have not included
absolute perfectionism as an ethical norm precisely because it is so religious,
whatever philosophical merit it might have.
Although
we avoid using absolute perfectionism as a norm, we can nevertheless look
approvingly at people who seem to act out of a high degree of deontologism, of
faithfulness to internal law, or of virtue. They are, as far as we know, better
people, but for most purposes of life it is sufficient to be good
enough people with our good actions.
The
following procedure is from ÒAn Approach to Ethical Decision Making,Ó a World
Wide Web file of the Markkula Center for Applied Ethics, Santa Clara
University, dated November 7, 1996:
Recognize a Moral Issue
*
Is there a conflict at the personal, interpersonal, institutional, or societal
level? Is there a question that
arises either at the level of thought or of feeling?
*
Does the question have a moral or ethical component? Why? (e.g., does it raise
issues of rights, moral character, etc.)
Begin Your Decision Making
*
What are the relevant facts of the case?
Whose (or what) interests are at stake?
*What
alternative actions are available?
What would other persons of good judgment think of your list of
alternatives?
Evaluate the Alternative
Actions from Various Moral Points of View
*
Which alternative would help one develop and maintain valuable traits of
character (e.g., be a person of courage or compassion)?
*
Which alternative would lead to the best overall consequences?
*
Which alternative best respects and protects the moral rights of individuals?
*
Which alternative treats all parties in a fair or just manner?
*
Which alternative best promotes the common good?
*
Which alternative would make a good general rule for people to follow in
similar situations?
Make a Decision
(After taking into account
the two questions below)
*Considering
these various points of view, which of your alternative actions would be the
best?
*
What would other persons of good judgment think of the justification of your
decision?
Consider Your Action in
Retrospect
*In
retrospect, was the action - and its results for others as well as your own
moral character - the best action?
*
What do other persons of good judgment think of the action and its results in
retrospect?
Dilemma resolution
The
greatest single problem of ethics, the one which is the most vexing and the
most challenging, is that of the ethical dilemma. This arises when an action is seen to be unethical by at
least one norm and there is no alternative which does not suffer from the same
defect, but it is necessary to act or it would be unethical not to act. The dilemma can be of the individual
who sees the vitiated alternatives, or it can exist among several people who
must act together but have diverse ethical judgments concerning the proposed
action.
The
basic principle of ethical dilemma solving is simply that if none of the
actions is good, the lesser of evils has to be chosen, that is to say that
choosing the lesser of evils is a good in the circumstances because to some
extent it prevents evil.
Prevention of evil is, by any norm, a good action. If, however, it cannot be shown that
any of the evils is lesser than others, then it makes no difference ethically
which action is taken. In this case
we do not say that a bad action becomes a good one; we say that the acting
person is not responsible for the bad action. In the former case the acting person who did not
choose the least of the evil actions would be responsible for the evil done
which could have been prevented. I
do not propose this analysis as being original, but I do not know of particular
sources to credit for it. It
should be noted that the reverse also applies. That is to say, that if all alternatives involve the same
evil, but one involves doing more good than another, then this fact does not
change the dilemma solving analysis of the least evil, but it does include
greater responsibility for good.
In
some dilemmas, therefore, it is expedient to establish continua of measurement
of bad actions. Such might be the
amount of harm done to individuals by an action judged to be good according to
utilitarianism. It could also be
the violation of fairness due to claims of justice or respect owed some people
but not others. Again, virtue goes out first of all to certain persons, such as
relatives or neighbors, and it would be worse to exclude them from one's good
actions than it would be to exclude others. Any of these comparisons can be used to provide a solution
to the famous air raid shelter or lifeboat dilemma, in which someone has to be
left out.
This
is not to say that it is easy to establish such continua or that, although it
might not be difficult to establish them upon reflection, one is called upon to
act quickly, before reflection is possible. Even more difficult, however, than the individual's
accomplishing this feat is the difficulty there is when several people must act
together and do not agree ethically.
In this case rational negotiation is needed for deciding which norms
apply and, more often than not, for deciding which course of action produces
the least evil. If consensus is
not reached on this latter point, then the group acting cannot be held
responsible for the bad which is found in its action. This final conclusion seems counterintuitive to us, but I
judge that the reason it seems so is that we expect people to be able to agree
on ethical norms and we feel that there is something wrong if they do not, but
the fact is that it comes under the heading of the human condition that people
disagree as much as they do about fundamental and important issues. This being said, however, rational
negotiation is ethically sound and it arises from the positive side of this
same human condition.
How
to approach ethical dilemmas in the great human arenas of business, human
services, and politics is a matter of applied ethics. I do not judge that there
is a single ethical formula for all types of action. It appears, for instance, that in a free market society the
basic norm for judging business is utilitarianism, which must be tempered by
fairness, whereas in a socialist society the basic norm for judging business is
fairness, which must be tempered by utilitarianism.
In
The Prince, Niccol˜ Machiavelli makes some striking judgments which can
be interpreted as cynical and amoral.
He contends that the prince must be bad in some situations and that he
can indulge in certain vices to save the state (chapter 15), that he should be
miserly rather than liberal (chapter 16) and sometimes cruel rather than
merciful (chapter 17), that if he cannot be both loved and feared he should
choose to be feared (chapter 17), that if it is necessary to seem rather
than to be merciful, faithful, humane, sincere, and religious he should
do so and he must be ready to do evil if constrained to do it, and that in his
actions Òthe end justifies the meansÓ (chapter 18).
These
assertions, however, need to be understood against their background, which is
his observation - cynical or not -
that the prince has to deal with bad people, and if he had only to deal with
good people he would not have to do these things, but could do the good as he
sees it (chapter 15). Furthermore,
the prince is to undertake all these bad actions for the good of the state
(chapter 15). Although we must
beware of anachronisms in our understanding of Machiavelli, it does not seem
inaccurate to call this a rudimentary notion of utililarianism. He was not in a position to clarify
this because the ethical norm with which he was familiar (other than the
precepts of the Church) was virtue, and there was no way he could reconcile the
norm we would call utility with that of virtue. Actually, his statement that the prince is constrained to
perform these bad actions (chapter 18) is as much as to say that he is not
responsible for their evil, i.e., that he is absolved of responsibility for the means because it
is not within his power to change the fact that they are the means to a good
end. Thus, MachiavelliÕs
incitement to the prince to do these things is better understood as a case of
dilemma resolution than as a conflict of norms.
Maxims
A
terse statement of each ethical norm is a rule of conduct, a maxim. As we have seen, each norm of the
common Western ethical patrimony is applicable to a certain field of
situations, and, within these boundaries, each is a maxim. In the sense of Aristotelian logic each
is a major premise, a principle, from which conclusions can be deduced. This line of thinking, we have already
observed, is all right as far as it goes.
Its main defect is that it cannot deal with dilemmas. The principle I have proposed for
dealing with dilemmas, however, is not of itself a norm but a means of weighing
responsibility.
Furthermore,
the collection of norms of ethics does not point to a metaprinciple, a
supernorm, a source ethical statement from which the norms can be deduced. Normative statements which are so broad
as to extend to all norms are so vague that they have no useful content. Such is "Good is to be done; evil
is to be avoided," which tells you nothing about how to discern good from
evil. A reading of Robert Nozick, Philosophical
Explanations, p. 477, suggests the correlative notions that no single
principle can found all ethics (possibly even no set of principles) and that
deduction from ethical principles cannot solve all ethical problems. Martha Nussbaum's Love's Knowledge
also treats this at length.
Even
the assertion that good actions
are those which unify, does not lead to the norms by way of deduction, but by
way of the analysis of the components of action, by way, that is, of relationship.
This
leaves us with the possibility that some maxims might summarize, epitomize, or
synthesize all or at least some of the norms. Any such limited summaries, it is clear, would both help our
minds to deal with the whole of a situation and help them grasp more aspects of
it and be more aware of people who might be affected by our action.
The
foundation on which such maxims rise consists of elements which are shared by
norms. The elements which are
different, such as diverse kinds of outcomes, will not help locate them, but a
search for the common elements ought to do this. It seems to me that to engage in such a search would be an
interesting enterprise, and probably a fruitful one. For the purpose of this chapter it is sufficient to treat
briefly three useful general maxims.
The
first maxim is the categorical imperative. Wrested away from Kant's own narrow methodological and
psychological framework, the statement, "Act only on that maxim through
which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law"
and its equivalents, speaks of the external consequences of justice, fairness,
and respect as well as the internal motivation of duty, love, and pity. To Kant the categorical imperative was
more than a maxim, but from our point of view it is only a better, more
generally applicable maxim than some others. By taking Kant in this simple, obvious sense, we avoid the
deontology versus consequences polemics which center on him, and which, as we
have already asserted, do not correctly represent the realities of ethical
action.
Donald
Walhout states a maxim which is reminiscent of the categorical imperative:
"The moral standard may be expressed as follows: Act always in accordance
with the requirements of prudence, loyalty, benevolence, and justice - normally
in this hierarchy but allowing exceptions in priorities - and always act from agape
and universal piety throughout, so that the end of maximizing perfections to
the highest degree possible in the moral situation may be
accomplished." (The Good
and the Realm of Values, pp. 85-86.)
The emphasis in Walhout's maxim lies on virtue, love, and perfectionism,
but the virtues mentioned relate to the results of fairness and respect. Furthermore, prudence can counsel
utilitarianism. This maxim is
close to all embracing, but it is so at the expense of losing brevity and
simplicity.
The
golden rule, well known in its Christian formulation, "Do unto others as
you would have them do unto you," is an ethical maxim in use since
antiquity. Ancient philosophy and
folk wisdom also have various equivalent expressions of the golden rule. (J.O. Hertzler, "On Golden
Rules.") Robert Hume showed
eight variants of it from eight religious and philosophical traditions, such as
"Do naught to others which, if done to thee, would cause thee pain: this
is the sum of duty" (Hindu), "What you do not want done to yourself,
do not do unto others" (Confucian), "That nature only is good when it
shall not do unto another whatever is not good for its own self" (Zoroastrianism). (The World's Living Religions,
pp. 265-266.)
As
pointed out by commentators, the golden rule has a positive formulation,
"Do unto others as you would have them do unto you," and a negative
one, "Do not do unto others as you would not have them do unto you,"
but these two formulas are equivalent if they are taken not as relating to
particular desires but as expressing a general moral principle that we should
judge ourselves and others by the same rules, that we should not set up special
rules, privileges, for ourselves at the expense of others. Furthermore, merely taking the golden
rule as an injunction to do or avoid certain actions regarding others simply
because we favor or disfavor them ourselves leads to conflicts because of the
diversity of desires that people can have. Thus it has to be taken in the sense of a general ethical
principle of consistency, fairness, or justice. The reason for being concerned about this is the valuing,
esteeming, or respecting of others like one's self on a basis of commonality,
but this also means that we must esteem our own selves, that we must have a
measure of self love as well as altruistic love (in Christian terminology,
"Love your neighbor as yourself"). (A. T. Cadoux, "The Implications of the Golden
Rule," Hertzler, "On Golden Rules," and Marcus Singer, "The
Golden Rule.")
Thus
analyzed the golden rule expresses an understanding of the relations between
self and others which enters into most - possibly all - the recognized ethical
norms. I found it useful in
teaching business ethics to explain how each of the ethical norms most useful
for analyzing the ethics of business situations, utility, respect, and
fairness, rests on the relationships expressed by the golden rule. This seemed to furnish the students
with the conceptual link needed to see the study of the norms of business ethics
as an intellectual activity and not just as a process of applying dissimilar
principles one by one
In
The Golden Rule (1996), Jeffrey Wattles shows the results of a very
extensive survey of the literature on the Golden Rule in English and other European
languages. He, for instance,
points to similarly broad, perhaps even broader, treatises in German. Most of the work is an historical
survey, which pays due regard to Confucian, Classical Greek, and Jewish thought
on the Golden Rule before it settles into detailed treatment of Christian and
modern European philosophical views on it. He takes pains to explain why the Rule, taken as a ÒprincipleÓ
(a ÒmaximÓ in the terminology of the present chapter) has to be taken in
contexts of meaning and of personal growth rather than as a metaethical
principle. He is most interested
in the religious significance of the Rule (such as its relation to the
brotherhood of man under the fatherhood of God), but this does not bias his
philosophical analysis.
Examples of the ethical analysis of human activities
Four
examples will be presented here.
Two concern problems from general ethics, one treats a problem from
business ethics, and the fourth deals with a complex question from health care
ethics.
The
pattern of each analysis is as follows:
Immediate
source of information
Summary
of facts
Clarifications
Ethical
questions involved
Central
question
Related
questions
Procedure
Ethical
analysis
According
to consequential norms:
eudaemonism
altruism
respect
fairness
justice
utility
According
to deontology
According
to virtues
self-control
conscientiousness
beneficence
In
order to avoid useless verbiage, as we analyze cases we shall pass over any step
of the method which is not needed and any norm which does not apply
MURDER
Clarification:
Murder in
the English language is taken to mean the unwarranted killing of another; an
action which by its very nature is unethical. Killing (another human being) may or may not be murder. Whichever of the two words we use as a
starting point the ethical issue is the same, although in either case it can be
expressed in two ways, ÒWhen is the killing of another unwarranted?Ó or ÒWhat warrants
the killing of another?Ó No end of
subtlety is possible with these questions, but we will approach them in a very
basic way by using our announced style of analysis.
Ethical analysis:
Eudaemonism/altruism - can
the killing of a person make that person happy (whether killed by self or by
another)? Before the fact,
yes; After the fact, no (at least
by the measure of observed and experienced human life)! Furthermore, killing a person cannot
make that person unhappy after the fact (once, again, by empirical
observation). Thus some acts of
killing are good by these norms, although the question of whether the killing
is warranted or not seems not to be touched upon by this part of the ethical
analysis.
Utility - utilitarianism in
its broadest, most understood form, ÒactÓ utilitarianism, readily and
disconcertingly concludes that the killing of some people produces the
greatest good of the population as
a whole. In actual cases other
norms contradict this exoneration of killing.
Fairness - this comes into
play in the supposition that someone or some group is inevitably to be killed,
that forces over which the participants judge that they have no control produce
a situation in which there will be death, and the question is, whose? Such is war, in which people assume
that they are being sent to kill or be killed. Similar is personal self-defense, in which the aggressor has
set up a situation which allows him to be treated as he would treat the other
person, i.e.,: to be killed. There
remains the matter of the ethics of war, but that is not the issue here. There also remains the possibility that
the individual aggressor is warranted in what he is doing, and so other norms
are still needed to determine the warrantability of killing.
Respect - in our society the
right to live is held to be possessed by all human beings equally. That is to say that noone has more
right to live than another, and noone has - other things being equal -
authority to take away this right from another. Moreover, a society which does not think in terms of rights
can hold in the place of right that of justice and assert that one may not take away anotherÕs
most precious possession, life, unless there is a preponderant reason for doing
so. Finally, a society which
thinks neither in terms of rights nor of justice can nevertheless hold respect
in a prominent position and can define the conditions under which respect is
compatible with killing. In one of
these forms or another, respect is the central norm in this matter. It is confusing, and perhaps
unfortunate, that respect is not viewed the same way in all societies, but this
does not mean that the idea of respect itself is relative. Thus, the practice of exposing aged
parents to the elements so that they die is perfectly compatible with a basic
idea of respect, although it is not necessarily (and not usually) compatible
with the more evolved ideas of respect as rights or justice.
Justice - no matter which of
the notions of respect is brought into play, it is possible to assert that if a
killing lacking in respect has taken place the balance of personal justice has
been upset and can be restored by requiring the perpetrator to undergo a
similar action. More advanced
societies restrict the right to take such action to the community. This restriction is of itself legal
rather than ethical, but the rule of law and the protection of law which it
reflects are arguably good for the common welfare, and thus ethical.
Deontology - unfortunately
experience teaches that many people in many times and places have killed others
with a good intention that the majority of impartial observers perceive to be
mistaken because these killings are bad according to other ethical norms. Deontology is not a reliable norm in
this matter.
Virtue - It seems
contradictory to assert that the virtuous person, the good person, exercises
goodness by killing, even if the killing is warranted. At the most it can be said that some
killings are acts of mercy or conscientiousness, but they are recognized as such
not by inspection of the goodness of the actor, but by application of other
ethical norms.
Conclusion:
The essential difference
between murder, unwarranted killing, and other killing lies in respect or the
lack of it, although other circumstances, including the codification of respect
among those involved, need to be considered in concrete cases.
LYING
Clarifications:
For the sake of ethical
analysis, to lie needs to be taken with the sense that it has in common
usage. No doctrinaire,
idiosyncratic, or technical sense will do. A general and eclectic definition of
lying is To lie is for a human person to express by s;eech or equivalent
sign to one or more others that a certain statement of the speakerÕs has the
speakerÕs assent whereas it does not, and this statement is made in order to
deceive the other(s).
Essential to this is communication: there must be an actual or
potential receiver of the message and awareness of dissonance: the
speaker realizes that the statement does not state what he judges to be the
case and intent of the speaker to deceive. There are speech acts, such as story telling, in which the
first two elements of the definition of lying are found, but the third is
not. We do not say that we lie
when we tell a story unless we tell it expressly for the purpose of
deceiving. The same goes for
flattery, although this is more closely associated with deceipt than story
telling is.
Ethical analysis:
Altruism - it is conceivable
that one person would deceive another in order to make the other happier. Such an act of deception, however, has
to be judged also in the light of the other ethical norms. It could, for instance, be demeaning.
Utility - it is conceivable
that a maximum of overall good could arise from a deception such as one that
puts many people at ease or that makes life more bearable or that helps people
acquire courage. Such acts of deception,
like those above, have to be judged also in the light of the other ethical
norms. They also could be
demeaning.
Respect - deception can be
demeaning, which is to say that it lacks respect, and probably this is most
frequently the case. Nevertheless,
it is possible to deceive someone out of respect for that person and not
necessarily to make the person happier, but, for instance, to make the person
better equipped to deal with difficult situations.
Justice - in many cases of
lying there is no question of justice, but if there is, then deception is
unethical. If an oath is taken,
for instance, it is a matter of justice to speak accurately and not to
deceive. Even without oaths, the
gravity of a situation can set up a situation in which one owes it to another
to speak without deception.
Deontology - application of
the consequential norms as above allows for the possibility that one is not
intentionally doing evil by deceiving.
Thus deceipt is not to be branded as inherently evil by intention, athough
it is sufficiently disruptive of communication that the presumption stands in
favor of its being unethical. In
other words, the question is, ÒWhy donÕt you speak your mind in the normal
communicative manner?Ó
Virtue - as might be
supposed by the above analysis, benevolence can be the very mainspring
of an act of deception. More probably, however, in the ordinary
course of events, is the non-virtuous use of deception to cover up ones
mistakes or to advance oneÕs self fraudulently.
Conclusion:
An act of lying is presumed
to be wrong, but unless it clearly violates one or more ethical norms it should
be examined for its ethical possibilities. To assert that every lie is evil is to oversimplify a
complex phenomenon of
communication.
MANIPULATION OF CORPORATE
REPORTS
Immediate source of information:
New York Times, ÒTruth or Consequences? Hardly,Ó by
Reed Abelson, June 23, 1996.
Summary of facts:
Some American corporations
make it appear by means of legal or illegal accounting practices that they are
more profitable than they are so as to please current investors and to attract
new ones. High executives of these
corporations are apt to profit personally from this because of performance
bonuses. The practices narrated in
the article include promising
unrecorded future discounts to customers who buy now at present prices,
including as revenue sales not yet made, not deducting the value of returned
goods, using unrecorded stock
warrants in place of cash payments, restructuring the corporation so as to
shift large financial obligations from the time they are incurred to other
times, hiding excess inventory.
Supplementary material presented in the article lists seven kinds
of accounting subterfuges: 1) recording
revenue before it is earned, 2) inventing fictitious revenue, 3) bolstering
income with one-time gains, 4) shifting current expenses into a future period,
5) failing to record or disclose liabilities, 6) using hidden reserves to
smoothen out incomes, and 7) accelerating expenses in a special restructuring
charge.
Clarifications:
The purpose of financial statements as treated in the
article is to report to the stockholders and other investors the financial
status of the corporation. Other
uses of financial statements, such as for tax and public policy purposes, are
not considered. Legality or
illegality of the accounting practices is not the question in this ethical
analysis except where legality and ethical goodness coincide.
Ethical questions involved:
Is it bad to issue financial
statements which mix the financial representation of accounting adjustments with that of operational gain or loss
so that those for whom they are written are not sure of the financial status of the
corporationÕs operations?
Questions secondary to this are ruled out by the clarifications stated
above. A complete treatment of the
ethics of finance and investment
would have much to say about them.
Ethical analysis:
Eudaemonism - Curiously,
this is a Òmake people happyÓ scheme, although the pleasing of stockholders and investors is done
for self-centered, not altruistic reasons, and altruism can be violated by
it. Thus, although eudaemonism is
in a sense present, it is not applicable as a norm.
Fairness - Although it is
said in the article that all companies engage in such practices, it is not said
that they all engage in comparable ways.
In fact some are notoriously more prone to these practices than are
others. Thus two corporations can
have the same situation but report it differently, one clearly and the other
unclearly, to the detriment of the more clearly reporting one. And so, fairness is violated.
Respect - Concern for
respect is perhaps best termed as respect for the rights of the stockholders
and other investors. The existing
stockholders certainly have a right to be told with exactness the status of the
corporation if they are to be told about it at all. The right derives from the relation of the corporation to
the stockholders, who are its guarantors as well as its beneficiaries. This right is violated by the practices
in question.
Justice - The consideration
of justice applies here to future contracts of buying and selling which will be
based on a distorted understanding of the status of the corporation. Because of these practices such contracts
will be flawed and unjust ethically
whether or not they are treated as such legally.
Virtue - What kind of people
are responsible for these practices?
Evidently , except for first-time perpetrators or ingenuous
businesspeople, they are people who place business relationships above human
relationships. While they may be
beneficent toward some persons, they lose the guidance of
conscientiousness. Furthermore,
regardless of the outcome of these practices, fiduciary trust has been placed
in the corporations and those who present their financial status, and this
trust is betrayed by them, another lack of conscientiousness.
Conclusion:
The practices presented in
the article are unethical, which is shown by the way they violate several
diverse ethical norms.
CREATION OF FOUNDATIONS
THROUGH THE SALE OF NOT-FOR-PROFIT HOSPITALS TO FOR-PROFIT HEALTH CARE
CORPORATIONS
Immediate source of
information:
ÓIn Hospital Sales, an
Overlooked Side Effect,Ó by Tamar Lewin with Martin Gottlieb, New York Times,
April 27, 1997.
Summary of facts:
Large for-profit health care
corporations in the United States have been buying smaller not-for-profit
hospitals . When such a sale
occurs, according to American law, the proceeds Òmust be put to charitable use, to repay the public for
years of tax exemptions and donations.Ó
It has happened that no apparent effort was made to establish a fair
market price for the sale of such hospitals and there was no profit at all
where there was reason to think that there should have been profit. When there are proceeds from the sale
they are placed into a new or existing charitable foundation, but in many
instances the directors of the foundation are the former hospital
administrators, the persons who negotiated the sale. In many of the
transactions the for-profit corporation buys half interest in the hospital and
takes over the administration completely.
This leads to possible conflict between the interests of the hospital
and those of the foundation.
Furthermore, the type of charity undertaken by some of these foundations
has nothing to do with health care, the premise under which the not-for-profit
status had been secured. No
accusation has yet been made that any of these transactions has been illegal,
but the federal government and several state governments have begun to pay
attention to pending ones, contending that in the public interest they need to
monitor them and act if warranted.
Clarifications:
This phenomenon arises out
of the tax exempt status of not-for-profit hospitals in American law, a legal
matter that carries ethical responsibilities. The article does not question the quality of health care
delivered by any of the organizations involved and it does not question the
system of treating health care organizations as business entities; these are
matters which can be analyzed ethically, but not in the case at hand.
Ethical questions:
1. Is the tax law about the proceeds of
the sale of not-for-profit hospitals ethically good?
2. Is it ethically incumbent on those who
negotiate such sales to secure fair market value for them?
3. Is it ethical for hospital
administrators who negotiate the sales to become officers in the resulting
foundations?
4. Is it ethically necessary that the
foundations established by these transactions be exclusively or at least mainly
for health care?
5. If only a half interest in the hospital
is sold how can conflict between the interests of the foundation and those of
the new health care facility be avoided?
The
information given in the article is not sufficient to define the relationships
between the unsold half of the hospital, the health care corporation, and the
foundation, and so no ethical analysis of this question will be attempted here.
Procedure:
These questions lay
themselves out as a sequence of ethical implications of the not-for-profit
status. Instead of a central
ethical issue and related issues there are immediate implications and further
ones, some of which seem to have been newly discovered. Our procedure will be to go from the
most immediate to the most mediate as the sequence of questions presents itself
Ethical analysis:
1. Is the tax law about the proceeds of
the sale of not-for-profit hospitals ethically good? Would it be wrong not to have such a law?
Utilitarianism - a clear
instance of utility: the law works to have the maximum public good
secured. Such a law could be
dispensed with only if customs or other powerful agents served the same purpose
Fairness - application of
the law seems to base distribution of the benefits of the proceeds in the
communities where the public good is in question, and this is fair. If the public good elsewhere were to be
served fairness would be lacking.
Justice - to whom should the
proceeds go? Because of the legal
nature of the organization nobody has a claim to them. Even the taxing authority (mainly the
federal government) has by law recognized that there are no profits. Thus commutative justice, quid pro
quo justice, is not an issue here, although distributive justice, fairness,
is a concern, as above.
Virtue - conscientiousness
as a public virtue is present here: a government trying to observe fairness and
maximize utility.
Conclusion:
The law is certainly good,
and if it did not exist there would need to be some forceful substitute for it.
2. Is it ethically incumbent on those who
negotiate such sales to secure fair market value for them?
the maximum obtainable for them?
Utilitarianism - in a free
market society utility is observed by obtaining fair market value. Obtaining less than this can be
considered not to be a disutility if it is negligible in the overall market. The amounts of proceeds involved in
this phenomenon, however, are far from negligible, and their utility demands
that at least fair market value be secured. There are standard procedures of bidding and selecting that
must be applied to ensure this.
Obtaining the maximum for them, however, introduces extraneous factors
which are not integral to overall utility.
Respect - respect as rights
is not an issue here (although justice
is; see below), but respect in its basic sense of honoring others and their
accomplishments is a consideration because selling for less than fair market
value demeans the effort and status of those who labored to build up the
facility to have the value that it did.
Justice - the individuals
who negotiate the sale of such a facility are not its owners; they are agents,
and the position of an agent is to act on behalf of the facility and secure for
it its due. If they sell for less
than fair market price they fail in justice. Negotiating to obtain the maximum profit in the sale,
however, is not more just than obtaining the fair market price.
Virtue - acting as an able
agent is a matter of conscientiousness.
Conclusion:
The common ethics of the
free market system and the added respect due the persons who labored for the
facility demand that fair market value be obtained. They do not require more than that, although obtaining more
does not of itself violate any ethical norm and may demonstrate a higher degree
of respect.
3. Is it ethical for hospital
administrators who negotiate the sales to become officers in the resulting
foundations?
Fairness - if there is a
competition among qualified persons and the former administrators are selected
by impartial persons, fairness is
secured. Otherwise the
fairness of the process is at least suspect and would have to be verified in
each individual instance.
Respect - the persons who
sell the hospital do not thereby gain a title to respect. Because of their knowledge and skills,
however, they may lay claim to respect either as being capable of directing the
foundation or of directing the hospital itself as a unit of the health care
corporation. This would have to be
examined in each instance.
Virtue - Loyalty, which has
aspects of both benevolence and
conscientiousness, and which would work to the good of the foundation or the
hospital, could be strong in these persons. This would not be assumed, but should be demonstrable if
present, and if it is found, it could lead also to loyalty as a feature of the
selection process..
Conclusion:
As long as fairness is
observed, there is no conflict of interest in this action, and there may be
characteristics of the negotiators which make them particularly suited for
these positions.
4. Is it ethically necessary that the
foundations established by these transactions be exclusively or at least mainly
for health care?
Fairness - the foundation
distributes funds which have their origin in savings in the delivery of health
care and in related activities. By
related activities we refer to the close relationship that has often existed
between not-for-profit hospitals and the social and economic needs of their
clients. These were the needs of
the Òwhole person,Ó and not just medical problems. Distribution of foundation funds for such needs is consonant
with the former relationship, although secondary to it, as provision for these
needs was previously secondary.
Respect - respect for
persons who contributed to the non-profit hospitals as such, that is, with
charitable intent, is observed by funding the same kinds of activities which
were in or associated with the non-profit hospitals.
Conclusion:
The foundations should help
health care primarily, but can also help poor and otherwise needy persons. They should not be involved in
activities unrelated to the mission of the not-for-profit hospitals, although
this allows some latitude with regard to particular hospitals, not all of which
reached out in as many ways as they might have.
ETHICS AND THE
PHILOSOPHY OF INDIA
Introduction
The
philosophers of India, ancient, medieval, and modern, have dealt with a broad
range of philosophical questions.
Currents and schools of Indian philosophy are numerous and complex, and, of
course, sweeping generalizations about Indian philosophy as a whole are no more
valid than sweeping generalizations about Western or European philosophy as a
whole. Nevertheless, there is in
Indian philosophy a definite worldview, an original position, which can be distinguished from that of
Western philosophy, and this shapes its subsequent development. Both streams of thought begin to
develop answers to the basic questions of philosophy by considering how to
account for the problems of the One versus the Many and of Permanence versus
Change. While Plato and Aristotle
brought forth forms and sense objects, substance and accidents, which gave rise
to later distinctions like essence and existence, universals and particulars,
noumena and phenomena, their Indian contemporaries began from the distinction
between All and the manifestations of the All. The Indian approach dealt more directly with the One and the
Many, placing the problem of Permanence and Change in the background.
Aside
from its many fascinating details, the main thesis of Joseph CampbellÕs The
Masks of God: Oriental Mythology. is that onto a background of sun and moon
cults, and hunting and agricultural mythologies there arose, embedded in written
language in connection with, and providing a justification for, society and
rulers, around B.C. 3200 in Sumer a conceptual explanation of the relationship
between man, his world, and the source of the world. Rather quickly the general lineaments of the explanation
took several forms, deriving from the notion that all somehow proceeds from the
One. To the East (of Persia) the
All was thought to remain the One, but to the West it was thought to be
distinct. This was expressed in the mythologies and theologies of the principal
cultures, each in its way articulating the relationships between God, Cosmos,
and Man.
Another
apparent difference between the original philosophical inspiration of India
compared with that of the Greeks was the religiousness of the former. Whereas Greek philosophy was distinct
from Greek religious thought, Indian philosophical thought was and is never far
from its religious basis. Properly
speaking, however, since the Indians were quite able to distinguish
philosophical from religious thought, it is better to say that the source of
the Indian philosophical ideas was more closely linked to religion than was the
source of Greek philosophical ideas.
Ever since then Westerners have had difficulty in distinguishing Indian
philosophy from Indian religion, but this problem also occurred in Western
philosophy, particularly from the time that the Christian worldview became
generally accepted.
Sanskrit,
the language of the Indian scriptures, was a living language through the period
of the composing of the earliest sacred text, the Rigveda (1200-1000 B.C.) and
down to the time of its crystalization by the great grammarian Panini (4th
century B.C.) Its evolution,
however, was consciously decelerated before Panini in an effort to preserve the
integrity of the sacred texts.
With Panini the so called classical Sanskrit came into being and
remained the language of Hindu thought. (Burrow, p. 36.)
As
an Indo-European language, Sanskrit shares its basic structure with Greek and
Latin and, to a lesser extent, with the Germanic languages. Sanskrit grammar: declensions,
conjugations, gender and number; syntax: the ways that sentences are put
together and related to one another are altogether familiar to the knowing user
of these other languages, in spite of the fact that its alphabet is dissimilar
from theirs. From this we should
not anticipate that the particular genius of this language would lead to
philosophical analyses and syntheses appreciably different from those of the
other languages. Even so, one
could at least wonder if differences like the following two might not have some
implications for the way that classical Sanskrit describes the world: (1) Referring to later classical
Sanskrit (toward 500 A.D.): "The nominal phrase in which the meaning is
expressed by the juxtaposition of subject and predicate, without any verb
becomes increasingly popular. This
is particularly so in the philosophic liiterature, and since that language also
favours long compounds, we may find long passages of exposition in which the
only grammar consists of a few case inflections of abstract nouns."
(Burrow, p. 56) (2) "The
derivation of nouns by means of krt and taddhita affixes has become a well
established theory, and an interesting argument between [post Panini
grammarians] Sakatayana and Gargya is reported as to whether all nouns can be
derived in this way from verbal roots.
The former maintained that they could, and in spite of the cogent
arguments on the other side advanced by Gargya, this was the theory that
generally held the field in Sanskrit grammatical theory. It is a fact that a larger proportion
of the Sanskrit vocabulary is capable of such analysis than is the case in most
languages." (Burrow, p. 48.)
In
the present essay I quote Sanscrit words exactly as they are written - in
italics or not - but without the diacritical marks which are so common in
them. Where I use a Sanscrit word
outside a quote I adhere to the most common English language usage (Upanishads,
for instance, not Upanisads; Shankara, not Samkara).
The
source of the Indian worldview and therefore of the philosophies which arise
from it is Scripture, that is, the Vedas, the Brahmanas, the Upanishads,
and the epics, Ramayana and Mahabharata.
There are other Scriptures, but they are of lesser influence. A not too short, not too long
explanation of this is in chapters 2 to 4 of Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, History
of Philosophy: Eastern and Western.
ÒBut
what is Scripture? It is nothing
but the product of the sustained thinking and mature reflection, superb
inspiration and profound realization of saints and prophets. To them, to those extraordinary minds
[page break] that are wiser and purer than our own, nothing is a sealed book,
and even transcendental truths are known directly through intuition or
super-developed power of reasoning....
[W]ithout the help of the sages who themselves directly realized the
truth, ordinary individuals can never hope to learn of God.... [E]ven in the case of ordinary men, the
Indian philosophers insist on the need of manana or reflection and
logical reasoning, after sravana or acquisition of philosophical truth
from Scripture. After that, there
should be nididhyasana, constant meditation for direct realization of
that truth, first acquired, on trust, from Scripture and then logically tested.Ó
(Roma Chaudhuri in History of Philosophy: Eastern and Western, pp.
341-2.)
In
harmony with the common sources of religion and philosophy in India,
philosophy, even as it is distinguished from religion, has remained until this
day a closely knit fabric of principles and practice. As Karl Potter expresses it, ÒIn Indian thought, as in
classical and medieval Western thought, the theoretical and the practical
function in close harmony -- as opposed to the Western position in contemporary
times, where there are on the one hand detailed analyses of theoretical
problems with no indications of their relevance to practical concerns, and on
the other anxious reflections on lifeÕs problems without any systematic
attention to the investigation of the nature of things.Ó (Presuppositions of IndiaÕs
Philosophies, p. 45.)
Again,
ÒIn India, philosophy has always been regarded as an intellectual attempt to
synthesize the sciences and as an ethical effort to realize the highest reality
or attain Moksa. Philosophy is not
merely a speculation, nor is it indifferent to science and analysis. But along
with its intellectual acumen and scientific analysis, it also pays equal
attention to the practical aim of philosophic thinking, which is nothing short
of spiritual-realization, having attained which the aspirant rises above all
contradiction, thereby giving proper place to sciences, philosophy, and
mysticism.Ó (I. C. Sharma, Ethical
Philosophies of India, p. 194.)
Another
aspect of Indian philosophy is that
ÒIndians are by their very nature metaphysicians; no school or system
without metaphysics, or with an unsound or weak meta-] page break [ physics,
can flourish long in the land of spiritualism and sages, whose very sagacity
and greatness lay in unveiling the metaphysical mystery through Darsana,
or direct perception of the ultimate reality.Ó The author goes on to say that this accounts for the
disappearance of Buddhism from India.
(Sharma, Ethical Philosophies of India, pp. 125-126.)
To
return to the worldview of the Indian scriptures and the oneness of the
universe: all things are one and, especially, all humans are
individually and severally one along with the rest. We can accept this assertion in three
ways, 1) religiously, as a mystery to be accepted unquestioningly, the
implications of which are to be drawn out within the confines of religion, 2)
intuitively, as an infinitely profound statement that can be contemplated
limitlessly without intellectual elucidation, and 3) philosophically, as an
intellectual content that can be analyzed in order to show the relationships
between the one and the many, which we know from experience. Of course we can accept the primary
statement in all three of these ways
Epistemology
The
just mentioned second way of accepting oneness points to the key function of intuition
in Indian epistemology. Indians,
like other philosophers, describe intuition as the direct knowledge of that
which is there to be known, without an intermediate process of sensing or
reasoning . This concept of
intuition plays a very large role in Indian religion, and in this context it
tends to resemble mysticism as found in many religions. Beyond this, however, it is generally
characteristic of Indian philosophy, in contrast to Western philosophy, where
it is encountered only here and there.
From
the above it is clear that the basic epistemological question posed in Indian
philosophy is not something like, ÒWhat are the conditions whereby
knowledge is assuredly true,Ó but is more like, ÒHow does knowledge of
the Many relate to knowledge of the One.Ó
Furthermore, unlike Western philosophy, which has gradually assumed the
position that there is no ontology unless it is preceded by a satisfactory
epistemology, Indian philosophy is satisfied that it possesses from the
beginning a basic ontological position, and the role of epistemology is
subsidiarily to clarify that position.
It
is nevertheless helpful to have an understanding of the Indian notion of the unknown,
which is stated by D.M. Datta like this:
Philosophy,
like every other branch of knowledge, must necessarily be limited to the
discussion of what falls within consciousness, immediate and mediate. Our notion of existence is derived from
what is manifest in perception, inference, imagination, etc., i.e. from the
known, in the widest sense of the term.
Our notion of reality is obtained, as we say, by a further sifting of
the known with the criterion of non-contradiction. Yet it will be dogmatic to conclude that the known is
all. Our curiosity about the
unknown remains and goads us to increase the bounds of knowledge.
Some
philosophers point out that there is nothing beyond knowledge and that what is
called the unknown or the unknowable must [p.310] also enter the domain of
knowledge in order that it may be so referred to. The reply to such a puzzling argument would be that in order
to be able to refer to the unknown it is sufficient if it is known that it is
not known. In other words we must
at least distinguish between the knowledge of something as unknown from the
ordinary knowledge of something as known, and widen thus the ordinary meaning
of ÔknowledgeÕ. This wider
knowledge, the consciousness of the known and the unknown, can, therefore, be
regarded as the matrix out of which definite knowledge emerges.
It
is not reasonable, therefore to deny the unknown. The unknown must be recognised as somehow marking the limit
of every definite knowledge. If we
carefully attend to the emergence of positive consciousness we can realize that
our ideas take definite shape out of an indefinite background. Like a search-light our positive
attention reveals things out of a surrounding gloom, that is, the unknown,
about which we cannot make any assertion, except that it is beyond grasp.
Now,
if ÒabsoluteÓ be the name that we may like to give to the all-inclusive that
covers the known and the unknown, we cannot say that it is wholly amenable to
the categories of thought. In so
far as this enters the logical pale of definite and systematic thought it
assumes a logical character; but even the whole of what enters definite
consciousness is not logical or real, as we have previously seen.
Philosophy
tries to know reality by reasoning that obeys the laws of logic. But it should only bear in mind the
limits of human knowledge and logical thought. The moral effect of such an attitude on philosophy would be
humility that would prepare the mind for new and unexpected revelations of the
absolute and remove cocksureness which more than anything else stands in the
way of the attainment of truth. As
in religion so also in philosophy the self, as a knower and reasoner, has to
recognise its limitations and helplessness, and ultimately surrender itself to
the Absolute for sharing as much of it as the Absolute chooses to reveal.(D.M.Datta
in Contemporary Indian Philosophy, p. 309-310.)
Ontology
When
it comes to ontology itself, it is important for the Western student to
appreciate the subtlety of the Indian philosophical explanations of the
relationship between the One and the Many. There are five recognized schools of
thought in the Vedanta or mainstream of Indian philosophy which accepts the
Oneness of the universe from the Upanishads. As expressed by Roma Chadhuri,
ÒThere
are five main schools of the Vedanta, viz. SamkaraÕs ÒKevaladvaita-vadaÓ
or strict Monism, RamanujaÕs ÒVisistadvaita-vadaÓor qualified Monism,
NimbarkaÕs ÒDvaitadvaita-vadaÓ or Dualism-Monism, MadhvaÕs ÒDvaita-vadaÓ or
Dualism, and VallabhaÕs ÒSuddhadvaita-vadaÓ or pure Monism. The main question here is as to the
relation between Unity and plurality, God and the world: Whether there is a
relation of absolute non-difference (abheda) or absolute difference (bheda)
or both (bhedabheda) between them.
Briefly, according to Samkara, Brahman alone is true, the world is
false, so that the latter is absolutely non-different from the former. According to Ramanuja, the world is real like Brahman, and
both non-different and different from it, but here the stress is more on
non-difference. According to
Nimbarka, too, the world is real and both non-different and different from
Brahman, but here stress is equally on both non-difference and difference. According to Madhva, the world is
absolutely different from Brahman.
According to Vallabha, the world is real and non-different from Brahman.Ó (History of Philosophy: Eastern and
Western, p. 343.)
From
a Western point of view, the most extreme of the five Vedanta schools is that
of the 8th century philosopher Shankara, who is considered the greatest
philosopher of the Indian Middle Ages. His strict monism logically entails the
view that the world is mithya or illusory in contrast to Brahman, the
One. Nevertheless, ÒWhat Sankara tries to point out is
that the world as the Vivarta [vivarta: an effect that is different from its
cause] of Brahman is neither absolutely real because it is just a Vivarta nor
is it abolutely unreal because it is not imaginary like the horns of a hare or
like the son of a barren woman. It
is therefore relatively real. As compared with the imaginary entities like the
horns of a hare it is real, but as compared with the Absolute Reality of
Brahman it turns out to be as false as the snake apears to be false when the
man under the illusion becomes conscious of the underlying reality of the rope.Ó
(Sharma, p. 252.)
ShankaraÕs
notion of a monism which includes relationships cries out for explanation. ÒThough Samkara said that the
world was maya and was due to maya, and though some of his
followers were more or less satisfied with that statement and turned their gaze
towards the inner absolute Reality, most of them could not resist the urge for
a conceptual construction of the world even on the basis of the concept of maya. The latter treated maya, not as
a concept of value, but as a principle of explanation and creation. However mysterious it may be, its
working must have a method, which they wanted to grasp rationally.
ÒMaya
indeed means inexplicability. But
because it was used as a concrete term and because of its association with prakrti,
which is the root cause of the world, some followers of Samkara felt that,
along with the Brahman it should somehow be the explanatory principle of the
causation of the world. (P.T. Raju, in History of Philosophy: Eastern and
Western, p. 292.)
Although
the other Vedanta schools of philosophy are not pure monisms their explanations
of why the Many are and are not distinct from the One are sufficiently similar
that they share the same flow of thought from ontology to ethics. Although ours is a brief treatment of
general Indian ontology, we can, however, note the thought of a modern Indian
philosopher, S.K. Maitra, as representative of the heuristic value of the
Vedanta position. Maitra says
about the nature of reality, ÒIt
was the bane of contemporary Western philosophy that the real problems of
philosophy were lost sight of in the controversy relating to the claims of the
rival human faculties to the knowledge of truth. The true problem of philosophy was: What was the nature of
reality? Was it existence or was
it consistency or was it something else:
Bergson threw consistency to the winds, whereas, for Hegel, consistency
expressed the true character of reality.
The view to which I was gravitating was that there was one dimension of
reality which was hidden from the gaze of both these philosophers or at least
to which they had not paid sufficient attention, which really [p. 385]
contained the essence of reality.
That was the dimension of value.
This was also, I felt, the central teaching of the Upanishads, which had
insisted upon calling reality satyasya satyam, the truth of truth,
thereby indicating that it was not to be identified with the surface reality of
existence. So also, another
explicit statement of the Upanishads, Ônaisa tarkena matirapaneya,Õ Ôthis
knowledge cannot be obtained by reason,Õ expressed clearly that it could not be
identified with consistency. What
it was, was indicated in the systematised Vedanta by the word
Saccidananda. This conception of
Saccidananda was perhaps the grandest achivement of our ancient culture.
ÒIt
was a condensed formula which indicated more tersely than anything else could,
the essential nature of reality.
It showed that there were three dimensions of reality, namely, Sat
or the dimension of existence, Cit or the dimension of consciousness or
reason, and Ananda or the dimension of bliss or value. The whole standpoint which looked upon
Reality as Saccidananda might be called the standpoint of Reality as
Value. All reality had these three
dimensions. To regard reality as
only Sat or existence was to take a one-sided view of it. So also. to look upon it as merely Cit
was equally one-sided. Again to
take it as mere Ananda was to forget that it must be existent and must be
brought into contact with our reason or logicÓ. (Contemporary Indian Philosophy, pp. 384-5.)
The
Buddhist worldview derives from the Hindu one, but it is properly speaking
neither monistic nor non-monistic, because it has freed itself totally from
Upanishadic and any other kind of ontology. Its three presuppositions are pessimism (universal
suffering), positivism (nothing beyond the sphere of perception and reason;
repudiation of the Vedas and rituals), and pragmatism (preference for the
middle course, which is between sensual indulgence and rigorous
asceticism. (Sharma, pp. 155-8.) Still, if one wishes to emphasize Indian
philosophy rather then Hindu philosophy, Buddhism needs to be treated
explicity. Thus Pandit Tigunait in
Seven Systems of Indian Philosophy.
One
final observation about general Indian ontology is that its treatment of good
is much different from that of Western philosophy. Ever since Socrates tested the idea of the good in PlatoÕs
dialogs, the notion that there is a standard according to which all in the
world is judged permeates Western thought. India, however, did not develop its philosophy out of
Socrates and Plato. Taking inspiration
from the Rig-Veda, it acknowledges a structure in reality which is compatible
with its oneness: rta, the cosmic order. (Basham p. 102) Preserving or restoring this
cosmic order is the task of gods in popular Indian religion and of humans in
Indian philosophy. Actions which
achieve this end are called good by Indians, and we also can properly call them
that as long as we are aware of the difference between this notion of good and
the Western notion of it.
Philosophy of people and
society
Passing
into Indian philosophy of human beings and their society, we are struck first
and foremost by the insistence on the identity of humans with the One. ÒTat
tvam asi,Ó ÒThat thou art,Ó and ÒAtman [the human soul, spirit, or essence] is
Brahman [the One]Ó are to be taken quite literally. HumansÕ greatest problem and obstacle is avidya, or
ignorance about our true status, and our task is to dispel this ignorance so
that we are free to enjoy the One in us.
Out ultimate condition is called moksa, or liberation. The attainment of moksa is expected to
be a very long process extending over many lifetimes through the rebirth of the
soul in a series of other individuals until its karma or accumulated worth is
great enough to entitle it to moksa.
Not
only does Indian philosophy not dissociate the practical from the theoretical,
but it sets out explicitly to dispel avidya. Therefore it is correct to say, ÒHuman well-being is the
goal of Indian philosophy, whether it is to be attained through the logical
exposition of Nyaya, through the atomic analysis of the material world on the
part of the Vaisesika system, through the acceptance of the evolutionary nature
of the universe, ending in the emancipation of the self from the material
Prakriti, through the spiritual discipline of the Yoga, through the Karma
Kanda, the activistic view of the Mimamsa, or, lastly, through the saving
knowledge of Brahman as advocated by the Vedanta.Ó (Sharma, p. 179.)
In
the process leading from our present condition to moksa there are four
values or ends of life, ideals for us:
ÒThe four Purusarthas [purusartha: end or desire] are (1) Artha, or
wealth, (2) Kama, or satisfaction of desires, (3) Dharma, or moral duty, and
(4) Moksa, or spiritual perfection or liberation.Ó Artha and Kama are proper in the earlier stages of oneÕs
life, but at a certain point one must move to dharma in order eventually to
qualify for moksa. (Sharma, p. 78)
There
is one variant of Indian thought which offers earlier Moksa: Buddhism: ÒThe Upanisadic notion of Brahman, as
transcendental existence, into which the individual soul or Atman is merged at
the attainment of Moksa has simply been reasserted by the Buddha in propounding
the concept of Nirvana. What the
Buddha added was that this indescribable state of Moksa was in fact experienced
by him and could be experienced by each and every individual.Ó (Sharma, p. 167.)
A
final question about the Indian philosophy of people and society: if the perception that there are many
distinct human individuals is really an illusion to be dispelled by higher
knowledge, then how can there be a subject to whom ethical actions and their
consequences can be ascribed? This
is a question to be answered not by Western phenomenology, but on Indian
principles, by pointing to the subtlety of the Indian position that the world,
though mithya, is real in its way.
(David Cooper poses the question, but not an answer, in World
Philosophies, pp. 51-52.)
Ethics
Descriptive Approach to
Indian Ethics
The
sources of Indian ethics are the same scriptures that are the sources of Indian
philosophy. Furthermore the
scriptures contain many explicit ethical injunctions and evaluations which can
be considered concretely as they stand without analysis according to the
philosophical principles which link them.
If we read the Vedas, the Brahmanas, the Upanishads, the Ramayana and
the Mahabharata, including the Bhagavad Gita we see certain ethical themes over
and over again. I reduce to the following rather broad categories virtually
innumerable statements from the Indian scriptures and from commentaries on
them:
Non-violence
Control
of sensual tendencies
Tranquillity
or contentment of mind
Truthfulness
Positive
attitude (compassion, gentleness, tolerance, forgiveness and the like)
toward other human individuals
Respect
for the property of others
As
examples of actions considered ethical in the Vedas we can cite: ÒRigveda as
well as Atharva Veda mention honesty, rectitude, fellow-feeling, charity, non-violence,
truthfulness, modesty, agreeable speech, Brahmacarya (celibacy), religious
conviction, and purity of heart as the important virues that are praiseworthy.Ó (Sharma, pp. 72-3.)
A
list of Òmoral accomplishmentsÓ found in the epic Mahabharata is considered to
be a list of kinds of truth:
ÒTruth has been described to be of thirteen kinds (1) truth as equality, (2) as
self-restraint, (3) as absence of jealousy, (4) as forgiveness, (5) as
shamefulness, (6) as patience, (7) as tendency to non-injury, (8) as
self-sacrifice, (9) as meditation, (10) as tendency to do good to others, (11)
as unperturbed ability, (12) as kindness and (13) as non-injury. Almost all the moral accomplishments,
having a social bearing, have been included in the category of truth.Ó
(Dasgupta, p. 36, citing the Udyogaparva, Ch. 37,17.)
That
portion of the Mahabharata known as the Bhagavad Gita is considered to be the
greatest exposition of Hindu morality.
In general the ethics proposed in it are too closely linked to the Indian
ethical norms which we have yet to treat for it to present simple lists of
approved actions, but one passage clearly names a number of virtues: ÒIntelligence,
spiritual vision, victory over delusion, patient forgiveness, truth,
self-harmony, peacefulness, joys and sorrows, to be and not to be, fear and
freedom from fear, harmlessness and non-violence, an everquietness,
saisfaction, simple austerity, generosity, honour and dishonour: these are the
conditions of mortals and they all arise from me {Krishna]Ó. (Bhagavad Gita, 10, 4-5.)
Among
ancient schools of Indian thought Buddhism, as is well known even among
Westerners, emphasises compassion, which it proposes as the proper
stance to take in view of the great suffering of the world and the circle of birth
and rebirth in which humans are trapped.
Compassion has the power to break the circle and allow liberation.
Jainism,
another ancient, but small school that is amazingly resilient, is known to call
for extreme asceticism for a reason which can be expressed quite
briefly: ÒStrong diseases require
strong remedies; even so the sufferings, disease, fear, famine, death and
destruction which caused untold miseries could be stopped or prevented only by
attaining Nirvana, freedom from from rebirth and transmigration. This strong feeling made Mahavira [6th
century BC, founder of Jainism]advocate an abrupt renunciation and the
strictest possible ascetic life for the aspirant.Ó (Sharma, p.124.)
Non-violence
carried to its extreme is the signature of the most notable Indian of modern
times, Mohandas K. Gandhi. The
depth of the philosophical/religious has been explained as follows: ÒUsually the metaphysical aspect of
non-violence is lost sight of, and people are misled to believe that Gandhi
preached the pacifistic philosophy of meekness and non-resistance. If somebody
slaps you on the left cheek, turn your right cheek towards him. There is no doubt that Gandhi was
influenced by Christian ethics and that he was a true living Christian in one
sense. But he was more a mystic in
the practical sense and had realized through experience that non-violent
behaviour, when inspired from the innermost recess of the human personality, is
mightier than the mightiest weapons on the face of the earth because then it
rises from the central force, the spirit of man, which is in fact the central
reality and the central truth, God.
That is why he identified non-violence with truth and the truth with
all-pervasive God. If God as truth
is the basis and the background of the universe and man, the only way to
Godliness is the life of non-violence and love, and hence God, Life, Truth and
Love are identical, and all are again the ultimate Good.Ó.... (Sharma, p. 327.) ÒGandhi never explained his notion of
liberation or Moksa, because his aim, like that of the Buddha, was not
metaphysical exposition, but practical eradication of suffering, the well-being
of humanity.Ó (Sharma, p.330.)
Carvaka
is an ancient school of Indian thought that went against all the others by
asserting pure materialism. Recognizing only the first two purusarthas, artha
and kama, Carvaka ethics is a
logically consequent hedonism.
(Sharma, p. 109.)
Ethical Norms
Two
basic norms of ethics arise from Indian philosophy of people and society. The one is the dispelling of avidya,
and so anything that facilitates seeing the truth and avoiding illusion is
ethical (we shall deliberately avoid saying good lest we introduce the
Western point of view that we associate with the concept of good). The role of this norm is is so evident
from almost everything written about Indian ethics that it has been supposed
that it is the only Indian ethical norm.
The
very concept of moksa,
liberation, becomes explicit in the Upanishads {S} Sharma, p. 88. The ethical content of the Upanishads
consists principally of teaching about the actions which are necessary in order
to prepare one for liberation, such as self-renunciation (Tapas), charity or
philanthropy (Dana), right conduct )Arjavam), non-violence (Ahimsa) and
adherence to truth (Satya Vacanam).
(Sharma, p. 93.)
The
school of Yoga provides techniques that lead toward seeing the truth and
avoiding illusion. Thus, ÒIt is
only when the mind is absolutely free from mental modifications and is at the
Niruddha level that the complete control of body, mind, senses and the ego is
attained, and the yogin experiences calmness of mind. At the Niruddhavastha there is complete cessation of mental
modifications, and the state of Samadhi aroused thereby is called Asamprajnata
Samadhi, in which nothing is known or thought by the mind. It should be remembered that the
cessation of mental modifications, and the absence of any object or thought in
the Asamprajnata Samadhi, is in fact indicative of its positive aspect as the
highest knowledge of the self, which cancels the relative knowledge of objects
and other thoughts.Ó (Sharma, p.
207.)
ÒThe
Yoga system admits the following five Yamas or restraints;
(1)
Non-violence, or Ahimsa;
(2)
Truthfulness, or Satya;
(3)
Non-stealing, or Asteya;
(4)
Continence, or Brahmcarya and
(5)
Non-possession, or AparigrahaÓ (Sharma, p. 208)
Shankara
states something similar. ÒSamkara
explains that the antecedent conditions without which no one is authorized to
enter upon the knowledge of Brahman, are four. The first prerequisite for a spiritual aspirant is
designated ÔSadasad VivekaÕ, i.e. discrimination between the permanent and the
impermanent nature of things. The
second qualification is freedom from attachment to sensual pleasures whether
here in the material world or hereafter.
The third qualification is the cultivation of virtues like peace of
mind, self-control, endurance, alertness and faith (Sraddha). The fourth prerequisite of an aspirant
is a strong desire, or yearning for Moksa. This explanation of Samkara is usually overlooked by those
who wrongly believe that he derides or derogates action or morality in
comparison with the knowledge of Brahman.Ó (Sharma, p. 256.)
The
other norm is dharma. While it is
true that dharma has a number of closely related meanings in Indian philosophy,
the meaning here is, according to Arthur Basham, ÒDharma, the religious
and social duty of a good Hindu, is the common thread running through Hinduism. The origins of dharma lie in the
Rg-vedic concept of rta, the course of things or the cosmic order, the
maintenance of which was entrusted to the god Varuna. Derived from the sanskrit root dhr -- to bear, to
support, to maintain -- the word dharma has the literal meaning of that
which is established, that is, law, duty, or custom. The concept pertained to everything that was right and
proper for a member of the Aryan community,Ó (Basham, p. 102.)
It
is important to recognize the ontology behind the notion of dharma. Without it, one might well accuse
Indians of a superficial ethics of caste and caste duties in every part of
their lives except their conscious efforts to dispel avidya. With it, one can understand why natural
actions such as seeking well-being and pleasure (artha and kama)
are ethical unless they are carried too far.
While
we need to be aware of the philosophical basis of dharma as a norm we do not
have to ignore the fact that the ethics of the Vedas reflected the customs of
the society which produced them. ÒIt
is quite evident from the study of the Vedas that the early Aryans did
recognize the family as a unit and did enjoin upon every member of the family
to do his duty conscientiously.
The members of a family, particularly husband and wife, ought to have
mutual respect and love, according to the ethics of the Vedas. The sons and daughters in the same
manner must have ]page break[ respect for parents and ought to obey their
orders. The members of the family
must be polite and respectful to each other. The wifeÕs status was held to be very high, and a woman was
often allowed to choose her husband.
It may be mentioned, however, that polygamy was thought moral and polyandry
immoral in Vedic times.Ó (Sharma,
p. 73-4.)
There
is a third norm of ethical conduct in Indian thought. It derives, not from the philosophy of people and society,
but directly from ontology: ÒStanding
on the rock of the spiritual oneness of the universe, Vedanta explains the
basis of Ethics. If we injure,
hate or cheat others, we injure, hate or cheat ourselves first. For this spiritual oneness we should
love our neighbours as ourselves.
Because love means the expression of oneness. When we begin to love others as we love our own self, we are
truly ethical. Then we do not
think that we have fulfilled the highest end and aim of life by eating,
drinking and begetting children like lower animals, but that the fulfilment of
the purpose of life consists in loving others disinterestedly without seeking
any return of love as we love our own self. Animal nature, which is extremely selfish, must be conquered
by moral nature through unselfish love for the real Self of others.Ó (Swami Abhedananda in Contemporary
Indian Philosophy, p. 62.)
Another
contemporary statement of this idea:
M.K. Gandhi was asked to write a statement about his religion,
and in so doing he states the basis, both religious and philosophical, of his
ethics: ÒThe bearing of this
religion on social life is, or has to be, seen in oneÕs daily social
contact. To be true to such
religion one has to lose oneself in continuous and continuing service of all
life. Realisation of Truth is
impossible without a complete merging of oneself in, and identification with,
this limitless ocean of life.
Hence, for me, these is no escape from social service, there is no
happiness on earth beyond or apart from it. Social service here must be taken to include every
department of life. In this scheme
there is nothing low, nothing high.
For, all is one, though we seem to be many.Ó (Contemporary Indian Philosophy,
p. 21.)
Another modern application of this idea is that
of Vivekananda (1863-1902). ÒOne
great innovation which Vivekananda introduced into the order [of Ramakrishna]
is compulsory social service which every novice had to do before becoming a
monk (samnyasin); and many do it even afterwards. Vivekananda got the idea from the Christian missions. Service of the poor is called the
worship of daridra-narayana (God as the poor), which is an application
of the ancient truth that the Divine resides in every man.Ó (P. T. Raju in History of Philosophy
Eastern and Western, p. 529.)
ÒThe
criteria of moral judgment [ in the Ramayana epic}appear to consist in (1)
consideration for the other world, (2) regard of the elite, (3) effect on other
peopleÕs morals, and (4) oneÕs own conscience and self-respect.Ó (Tarapada Chowdhury in History of
Philosophy: Eastern and Western, p. 80.) It seems to me that only the last of these introduces normative content that
differs substantially from the three norms I have just noted, and this last one
is not so much a norm as a statement about the existence of the moral subject.
Having
established the Indian norms of ethics, we can rather readily understand that
the norm of relationship to liberation is the principal one of them, the one to
which the others are subservient.
Yet the others are not to be slighted, and many statements about the
ethical person in Indian philosophy explicitly include all three. As a matter of fact, to Indians the
primary division of ethics is not exactly according to the norms, but according
to the three paths, contemplation, action, and devotion. The last of these denotes a strong religious
orientation, and the first two call for a practical mixture in the individual
of the search for truth (removal of avidya) and the effort to live as a whole
human being in society. One
frequently encounters the three paths in the Indian Scriptures and commentaries
on them.
Again, ÒIt is due to the prejudicial viewpoint
of Indian ethics adopted by some, perhaps most, western scholars that Indian
morality is identified with asceticism, other-worldliness, and withdrawal from
social responsibilities. It should
not be forgotten that almost all the schools of Indian philosophy advocated a
mean between the extremes of unlicensed indulgence in worldly pleasures and
complete renunciation of social life.Ó (Sharma, p. 155.)
Returning
to Shankara, we can observe
that ÒWhat Sankara has tried to
make explicit is the fact that when action is performed with the knowledge of
the Brahman, it brings about liberation and has absolute value. Virtues like self-control, charity,
compassion, etc., are means to the attainment of true knowledge, as accepted by
Samkara in his commentary on the Brahma Sutra. He also regarded these very virtues to be helpful for
Abhyudaya, or prosperity, besides being of assistance in worship and
meditation.Ó (Sharma 262)
Again,
Ò[ShankaraÕs] repeated statements with regard to the performance of duties on
the part of each and every individual, and the emphasis he laid on adherence to
Niskama Karma (action without attachment) even on the part of the man who has
attained Jivanmukti [liberation of the soul in this life], and whose actions
would not bind him to the world, amply prove that the highest goal of life was
the sublime state of selfless service, universal love, and freedom from
selfishness and narrowmindedness.
He never advocated seclusion and inactivity even for the Sanyasin or the
Renunciate. The central feature of
the ethics of the Advaita Vedanta [ShankaraÕs school] is that advocates a
cosmopolitan outlook on life, and explodes the traditional rigidity of the
caste system by preferring the life of spirit to that of custom.Ó (Sharma, p. 264.)
The
Mimamsa is a major school of Indian philosophy and religion which simply
accepts the Vedas as its authority.
It asserts that virtue Òis a conscious or semiconscious adjustment of conduct
to interest. It draws our
attention to the adoption of Artha
and Kama for the advancement of the secular life of the individual as well as
of society,and the adoption of Dharma for the attainment of Moksa. The former two values have social
well-being as the ideal and lead to Abhyudaya, or progress, and the latter two
values, of which Moksa is the highest, aim at spiritual well-being as the
ideal, culmination in Sreyasa, or eternal bliss. The fact is that social well-being is not the highest end, but
is the means to the attainment of the highest value of Moksa.Ó (Sharma, 229.)
It
remains true, however, that ÒFor
some reason or other, most of the religious leaders (acaryas), including
Samkara and Ramanuja, underestimated the value of karma-marga [the path
of action]. with the result that, in general, the aspirant after the Divine
developed indifference to action and values of the world; and this attitude
resulted in lack of interest in matters social and political. This is considered to be one of the
reasons for the political downfall of India.Ó (History of Philosophy Eastern and Western, p. 530.)
One
more note about M.K. Gandhi and the political value of non-violence:
The
technique of non-violence lies in suffering -- suffering with a view to purify oneÕs ownself on the one
hand, and to change the heart of the aggressor or the evildoer on the
other. The following six
prerequisites or presuppositions, as Gandhi termed them, are essential for the votary
of non-violence:
(1) It must be taken for granted that
non-violence is the law meant for the rational beings and is thus preferable to
brute force, which is the law of the jungle.
(2) The votary of non-violence must have a
living faith in God.
(3) Non-violence should be taken to be the
best defence of oneÕs self-respect and should not be used as the means to
protect oneÕs property or wealth.
(4) Non-violence implies self-sacrifice and
hence presumes the possession of other peopleÕs property and countries to be an
immoral act.
(5) The power of non-violence is available
to all, irrespective [page break] of caste , creed and age, provided that one
has an abiding faith in the God of love.
It should thus be accepted as the law of life.
(6) The law of love -- non-violence, which
is the law of life, is equally pragmatic in the case of community and in the
case of the whole humanity. (Sharma, pp. 332-3.)
Sanction for Ethical Action
In
view of the doctrine of karma, by which the good or evil which one does in this
life return and shape oneÕs future life in a series of transmigrations, one
realizes that sanction is an essential
part of Indian ethics even before one considers the ethical norms. The ultimately positive face of karma
is that, no matter how many lives it takes, the individual will ultimately
attain liberation, and this liberation is generally thought to be positive,
absorption in Brahman, rather than annihilation. (It has appeared to some that nirvana in Buddhism is
annihilation of the individual, but this is mistaken, because Buddhism simply
does not state and it does not care to state anything about the characteristics
of nirvana.)
One
particular application of sanction is made in the Ayurveda, which strongly
insists on the connection between morality (as clean living) and health. (Dasgupta, pp. 28-31)
ETHICS
AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF CHINA
The Chinese Language
It
is a revelation to someone accustomed entirely to the Indo-European languages
to find how great are the qualitative differences between these languages and
Chinese. Everyone knows that
written Chinese does not relate to spoken Chinese the way written English or
Latin or Greek, for example, relate to spoken English, Latin, or Greek. For philosophy, however, more
significant than this difference is the Chinese way of expression. Rather than centering on the subject
and applying to it the verb and other sentence elements as the Indo-European
sentence generally does, the typical Chinese sentence presents a thing word and
an action word as correlated aspects of one situation or reality. The Chinese equivalent of Òto beÓ is in
this regard one action word among many others. Furthermore, abstractions in
Chinese are not constituted from formulaic suffixes added to a root, but from
the juxtaposition of concrete words or word parts which become understood
abstractly. Possibly more
important, one should not expect to have from ancient Chinese philosophy
readymade answers to questions which had not yet occurred to it. As an example, E. R. Hughes points out,
ÒThe grammar of the Book of
Odes [one of the classics that preceded Confucius] is structurally simple,
so simple that one of the chief hindrances to its understanding has been the
failure of the Scholars to transport themselves into this semi-primitive
atmosphere. Thus ku, the
main word in succeeding ages for expressing sequence, is not found in this
sense in the Odes. The word
for expressing connection between two sets of events, one earlier and the other
later, is pi; and the contents point to a religious meaning as the
original one. Because a man did
such and such, therefore to be sure (pi) the gods did so and so. This contains a rudimentary sense of
logic, but it is a long way from the logic of a man who not only says, ÔBecause
A happened, therefore B happened,Õ but also thinks of Ôthe cause,Õ and then at
last achieves that triumph of philosophical sophistications ÔcausationÕ and
Ôcausality.ÕÓ (Hughes, p. xxviii).
As in Western philosophy, however, concepts were gradually developed to the
point where they become the bearers of philosophical investigation.
To
understand the following conclusion of Mou Bo, in his article, "The
Structure of the Chinese Language and Ontological Insights: A Collective-Noun
Hypothesis," note his explanations of terms:
p.
58, " 'Mereology' means the (mathematical) theory of the relation of parts
to the whole. Its two major
versions are S. Lesniewski's formal theory of parts and N. Goodman's calculus
of individuals."
p.
49, he explains that people, cattle, police are collective nouns, whereas water
and snow are mass nouns.
p.
52, "A collection-whole and a mass-fusion-whole have different ontological
structures: the former consists of (many) separate individuals, while the
latter consists of (much) inseparable and interpenetrating stuff; and they have
different part-whole structures to be discussed."
Thus,
In
sum, in this essay, I have argued for a collective-noun hypothesis to the
effect that (1) the denotational semantics and relevant grammatical features of
Chinese nouns are like those of collective nouns; (2) their implicit ontology is a mereological ontology of
collection-of-individuals with part-whole structure and member-class structure,
which does justice to the role of abstraction at the conceptual level and which
can be given a consistent meta-interpretation in terms of contemporary
conceptual resources; and (3) encouraged and shaped by the functions and folk
semantics of Chinese nouns, the classical Chinese theorists of language take
this kind of nominalist mereological ontology for granted; as a result, the
classical Platonic one-many problem in the Western philosophical tradition has
not been consciously posed in the Chinese philosophical tradition, and,
generally speaking, classical Chinese philosophers seem less interested in
debating the relevant ontological issues.
The mereological collective-noun hypothesis, I believe would provide a
more reasonable interpretation of the semantics of classical nouns than
Hansen's mass-noun hypothesis.... (pp. 56-57)
At
this point a note about English translations of Chinese is in order. There are, of course, the usual
problems of translation, especially that of needing to supply a circumlocution or explanatory note
where there is no exact equivalent word.
In a language as different as Chinese is from English this is a greater
challenge than it is in
translating - for example - from French or German. Another type of problem arises from the
fact that different Chinese philosophers use the same words in different
ways. There are words which are
fundamental to all three of the great streams of thought, Confucianism, Taoism,
and Buddhism, but which have diverse meanings in each. This source of confusion is by no means
peculiar to Chinese philosophers, but, taken together with the language
equivalency problem, it means that we must pay careful attention to the context
in order to interpret the meaning of the word in it and that we must expect to
find wide divergencies among English translations.
The Chinese Worldview
The
ancient and traditional Chinese view of the structure of the universe is of an
all-embracing, undivided Heaven, out of which arise, without dividing the
Heaven, and not by creation, the mutually opposed principles, Yin and Yang. By an interplay of Yin and Yang
the world as we observe it is born by means of a process which was
described in Chinese mythology, but which was generally considered outside the
range of interest of philosophy.
Chinese philosophical investigation, in fact, veered away from the types
of analyses of the data of observation which became the bases of Western
philosophy. As Fung Yu-Lan writes,
Whether
the table that I see before me is real or illusory, and whether it is only an
idea in my mind or is occupying objective space, was never seriously considered
by Chinese philosophers. No such
epistemological problems are to be found in Chinese philosophy (save in
Buddhism, which came from India), since epistemological problems arise only
when a demarcation between the subject and the object is emphasized. And in the aesthetic continuum, there
is no such demarcation. In it the
knower and the known is one whole.
ÒThis
also explains why the language used by Chinese philosophy is suggestive but not
articulate. It is not articulate,
because it does not represent concepts in any deductive reasoning. The philosopher only tells us what he
sees. And because of this, what he
tells is rich in content, though terse in words. This is the reason why his words are suggestive rather than
precise. (Fung, p. 25.)
Furthermore
this makes it clear why the classical Chinese mind never had to wonder if truth
might be some kind of conformity between an inner, psychological, world and an
outer world and if our senses are truthful or not and if there is another world
out there which is different from the world we perceive ourselves to live
in. There were, however, a few
prominent Chinese philosophers who treated logic and the processes of thinking.
Angus
Graham writes of Òthe Chinese
tendency... to treat things as divisions of the universe rather then the
universe as the aggregate of things.Ó (Graham, p. 286) He states that he is following the lead
of Chad Hansen, who wrote, ÒThe mind is not regarded as an internal picturing
mechanism which represents the individual objects in the world, but as a
faculty that discriminates the boundaries of the substances or stuffs referred
to by names. This Ôcutting up
thingsÕ view contrasts strongly with the traditional Platonic philosophical
picture of objects which are understood as individuals or particulars which
instantiate or ÔhaveÕ properties (universals).Ó (Hansen, p. 30., quoted in
Graham, p. 401) Hansen arrives at
his notion of the Chinese mind through considerations of the Chinese language,
and although Graham does not entirely agree with these considerations, he
attaches great value to this insight into the Chinese mind itself. (Graham, p.
401) As Walter Benesch puts it, ÒFor
the Taoist in particular and in Chinese philosophy in general, the ultimate
ÔgivenÕ is orderly change in which the task of philosophy and science is to
establish Ôidentity in changeÕ and not Ôchange in identityÕ. Here there is an emphasis upon aspects
and the complementarity of opposites.
A perspective upon distinguishing and naming are important whenever
distinctions are made and names are applied. Objects are their functions and their functions are
expressed in naming.Ó (Benesch, p. 182)
It
certainly does not seem fruitless to speculate that the structure of the Chinese
language had something to do with the lack of interest in metaphysical analysis
as this was practiced in the West.
It appears, for instance, that the relation between action word and
thing word stresses the unity between subjects and their actions - or between
actions and their subjects - rather than their differences. This manner of expression renders unnatural any
discourse based on such distinctions as that between substance and nature,
essence and existence, and being and becoming. Furthermore, the making of abstractions not by an
abstractable generality that is found normally in abstract words, but by
juxtaposing concrete words ought to give less stimulus to see the abstractions
as things, whether inside the mind or outside it.
Although
ontology, the philosophy of being, and general philosophy of the observable
world were foreign to classical Chinese philosophy, and epistemology, the
philosophy of knowledge, was a minor concern to it, the remaining branches of
philosophy, that of people and society and that of human action (ethics), were
of passionate interest to it.
These two branches were scarcely separable and were, one might say, two
facets of the same study.
The
traditional structure of Chinese society with its five main relationships,
ruler-subject, father-son, older brother-younger brother, husband-wife,
friend-friend, was understood to be the embodiment of the heavenly order on
earth. Maintenance of this order
is the ontological basis of Chinese ethics. As E. R. Hughes puts it, Ò... Classical thinkers were plainly never able to get far
away from the idea of Nature as transcendent. Although they consistently rationalized the old religious
concept of a TÕien (Heaven) which had a will for men, the meaning of TÕien,
and even of Ti (Earth), retained the idea of a sublime order of the
universe, conformity to which was manÕs duty and happiness.Ó (Hughes, p. xxxiii.)
Furthermore,
the Chinese held the first action or development of primal Nature to be the
opposition of Yin and Yang, which passes its ontological value
into the world in the process by which extremes generate extremes. The process
of extremes generating extremes is seen in the natural rhythms of life (seasons, etc.), in the vicissitudes
of life (e.g., famine follows plenty and the reverse, riches follow poverty and
the reverse, and in the natural consequences of human action: having too much
or overdoing things will produce the reverse). This process is in turn the ontological basis of a key
general norm of ethics, which is that there is for man a golden mean of action
which avoids the process. (Fung, pp. 19-20)
Lastly,
[Chinese philosophy] Òis at one and the same time both extremely idealistic and
extremely realistic, and very practical, though not in a superficial way.
ÒThis-worldliness
and other-worldliness stand in contrast to each other as do realism and
idealism. The task of Chinese
philosophy is to accomplish a synthesis out of these antitheses. That does not mean that they are to be
abolished. They are still there,
but they have been made into a synthetic whole. How can this be done?
This is the problem which Chinese philosophy attempts to solve.
ÒAccording
to Chinese philosophy, the man who accomplishes this synthesis, not only in
theory but also in deed, is the sage.
He is both this-worldly and other-worldly. The spiritual achievement of the Chinese sage corresponds to
the saintÕs achievement in Buddhism, and in Western religion. But the Chinese sage is not one who
does not concern himself with the business of the world. His character is described as one of
Ôsageliness within and kingliness without.Õ That is to say, in his inner sageliness, he accomplishes
spiritual cultivation; in his kingliness without, he functions in society. It is not necessary that the sage
should be the actual head of the government in his society.Ó He goes on to compare the sage to the
Platonic philosopher-king. (Fung,
p. 8.)
In
writing specifically about ethics in Chinese philosophy Fung Yu-lan states:
Every
individual has his own sphere of living, which is not quite the same as that of
any other indivdual. Yet in spite
of these individual differences, we can classify the various spheres of living
into four general grades.
Beginning with the lowest, they are: the innocent sphere, the
utilitarian sphere, the moral sphere, and the transcendent sphere.
A
man may simply do what his instinct or the custom of his society leads him to
do. Like children and primitive
people, he does what he does without being self-conscious or greatly
understanding what he is doing.
Thus what he does has little significance, if any, for him. His sphere of living is what I call the
innocent sphere.
Or
man may be aware of himself, and be doing everything for himself. That does not mean that he is necessarily
an immoral man. He may do
something, the consequences of which are beneficial to others, but his
motivation for so doing is self-benefit.
Thus everything he does has the significance of ultility for
himself. His sphere of living is
what I call the utilitarian sphere.
Yet
again a man may come to understand that a society exists, of which he is a member. This society constitutes a whole and he
is a part of that whole. Having
this understanding, he does everything for the benefit of the society, or as
the Confucianists say, he does everything Ôfor the sake of righteousness, and
not for the sake of personal profit.Õ
He is the truly moral man and what he does is moral action in the strict
sense of the word, Everything he
does has a moral significance.
Hence his sphere of living is what I call the moral sphere.
And
finally, a man may come to understand that over and above society as a whole,
there is a great whole which is the universe. He is not only a member of society, but at the same time a
member of the universe. He is a
citizen of the social organization, but at the same time a citizen of heaven,
as Mencius says. Having this
understanding, he does everything for the benefit of the universe. He understands the significance of what
he does, and is self-conscious of the fact that he is doing what he does. This understanding and
self-consciousness constitutes for him a higher sphere of living which I call
the transcendent sphere.
Of
the four spheres of living, the innocent and the utilitarian are the products
of man as he is, while the moral and the transcendent are those of man as he
ought to be. The former two are
gifts of nature, while the latter two are the creations of the spirit. The innocent sphere is the lowest, the
utilitarian comes next, then the moral, and finally the transcendent. They are so because the innocent sphere
requires almost no understanding and self-consciousness, whereas the
utilitarian and the moral require more, and the transcendent requires
most. The moral sphere is that of
moral values, and the transcendent is that of super-moral values.
According
to the tradition of Chinese philosophy, the function of philosophy is to help
man achieve the two higher spheres of living, and especially the highest. The transcendent sphere may also be
called the sphere of philosophy, because it cannot be achieved unless through
philosophy one gains some understanding of the universe. But the moral sphere, too, is a product
of philosophy. Moral actions are
not simply actions that accord with the moral rule, nor is moral man one who
simply cultivates certain moral habits.
He must act and live with an understanding of the moral principles
involved, and it is the business of philosophy to give him this
understanding. (Fung, pp. 338-9.)
The Canon of the Chinese
Classics
Unlike
the classics of India, with their epics and poems and speculative commentaries,
those of China are few in number, and they do not include religious epics. Tradition has it that the few early
classics that exist were collected by Confucius. These are the ÒÕfive booksÕ containing ancient records with
which Confucius worked, or reworked, namely, the Shu-ching {Shu-King) or
Book of Historical Documents, the Shih-ching (Shih-King) or Book of Ancient Poems, the I
Ching (Yi King) or Book of Changes, the Li-chi (Li-Ki) or Book
of Rites and Ancient Ceremonies (within which Genuine Living [Chung Yung]
itself is embedded as Chapter XXXI), and ChÕun ChÕiu or Spring and
Autumn, being the annals of the state of Lu.Ó (Bahm, Heart of Confucius, p. 15.)
With
Confucius there began to form the orthodox classical corpus of the ÒFour BooksÓ:
the Confucian Analects, the Ta Hsueh [Great Learning], the
Chung Yung [Doctrine of the Mean], the latter two being chapters
in the Li Chi (Book of Rites) and the Mencius. It took from the Han dynasty (206 BC to
220 AD), however, to the Sung dynasty (960-1279) to solidify this corpus.
Other
than the classics and the writings of various Confucian commentators there were
the primary Taoist works, the Chuang Tsu, composed around 300 BC, and
the Tao Te Ching, composed
about a century later, but attributed to Lao Tsu, a - probably
legendary - contemporary of Confucius.
Ethics in the various
schools of Chinese philosophy
Classical Confucianism
Summary on Confucius Himself
(lived 551-479 BC)
As
revealed from his teaching in its simplest form, in the Analects, he was
the first to promulgate the insight that man is a knowing moral subject whose
choices bring or do not bring him as an entity in the world order into harmony
with this order. He is traditional
and conservative in sofar as he accepts the already fixed Chinese social
hierarchy, but he introduces the notion of morality as a human participation in
the world order which lies behind the social hierarchy and he introduces the
notion of jen, Òhuman-heartednessÓ (Fung and Hughes) or Ògood willÓ
(Bahm) or Òinner moral forceÓ (Cooper), which is a stance of the individual in
which he consciously takes his place in the world order. Man is a knowing moral subject with
genuine choices in a fixed world order.
Confucius does not investigate, he does not question the world order
itself or manÕs ability to know it.
According
to the twentieth century Chinese philosopher Chung-ying Cheng, we can discern
three stages in ethics as proposed by Confucianism. First is manÕs awareness of himself as an object in the
world. Next comes his discovery of
himself as a subject, and upon this follows his effort to act responsibly in
the framework of the given world.
Confucius (as we have noted) is one of those who made the discovery of
the ethical self, and he offers the framework, which is the perceived social
order, including the role of the ancestors in it.. The author shows how these stages in Confucian ethics are
religious: the first is the realization of the human condition, with all its
negatives; the second is the belief in some power which enables man to
transcend that human condition, an internal power in Confucianism, an external
power in some other religions; the third is the appropriate putting into action
of that power. The reader is aware
that norms of ethics relate to the third stage; in some religions they are
furnished by the religious body, but in Confucianism they are the social
order. He points out that these
three stages are a valid process only if they relate to one another in some
ontological framework, and Confucianism, of course, has such a framework. (Chung-ying Cheng, New Dimensions of
Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy, Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1991, ÒThree Stages of the Development of Confucian Morality,Ó pp. 280-293.)
The
interplay between ConfuciusÕs jen, which in some contexts is translated virtue,
and other basic concepts of his concerning manÕs role in the family and in
society brings out a rich notion of virtue-based ethics. One aspect which is missing, however,
is an appeal to reasonÕs role in establishing a personÕs attitude toward
virtuous action. In this Confucius
can be contrasted with Aristotle, whose notion of virtue has many similarities
with his, but is lacking in ConfuciusÕs incorporation of human love (as
of parents for children). (Juyuan
Yu, ÒVirtue: Confucius and Aristotle.Ó)
Tseng Tsu (Fifth
century BC)
Tseng
Tsu, who apparently was born just about when Confucius died, had great
influence in promoting the extreme emphasis which Chinese society placed on
filial piety. In spite of this, he
stated ethical values as ÒEvery day I examine myself in three ways: whether in
my transacting of business for other men I have been faithful to them; whether
in my intercourse with my friends I have been true in word; whether I have not
passed on teachings which I have not mastered.Ó (From the Analects i. 4
as quoted by Hughes, p. 71.) Similarly,
according to the Ta Hsueh, which is attributed (although inaccurately,
it seems) to Tseng Tsu, ÒWhat is meant by Ôkeeping our purpose genuineÕ is to
prevent self-deception. We should
hate what is evil(1) and love what is good(2). This is called Ôappreciating oneÕs own nature.Õ Hence, the wise man guards his
intentions even when he is alone.Ó The footnotes to this are Ò1. Lit., bad
odor.Ó and Ò2. Lit., beautiful view.Ó (In Bahm, p. 137.)
Mo Ti (about 480 to about
380 BC) and Mohism
The
foundation and guiding rule of ethics according to Mo Ti is, ÒHeaven wants men to love and be
profitable to each other, and does not want men to hate and maltreat each
other.Ó and note that the word for
love here is ai, which expresses the feeling of love. (Hughes, p. 45.)
More
thoughts of Mo Ti: he believes in the social hierarchy, that all levels must
strive for the love of others, and that each level is kept in line by the one
next higher. (Hughes, pp. 47-49.) Thus, ÒIf the whole of society had mutual love without
discrimination, country would not attack country, clan would not throw clan
into confusion: there would be no robbers: sovereigns and ministers, fathers
and sons, all would be compassionate and filial. In this state of affairs it follows that the Great Society
would be well ordered.... Thus it
was that our ]page[ Master Mo said that be could not but urge that men should
be loved. (Hughes, pp. 54-55.)
The
Mo Tsu Book says: ÒTo love and benefit another is to have him follow on
and love and benefit you. To hate
and injure another is to have him follow on and hate and injure you.Ó (Hughes, p. 55), and ÒAssuming then that Heaven embraces all and gives food to
all, how could it be said that it does not want men to love and benefit each
other?Ó Hughes, p. 46, and ÒHence
I say that Heaven is sure to give happiness to those who love and benefit other
men, and is sure to bring calamities on those who hate and maltreat other
men. I maintain that the man who
murders an innocent person will meet with misfortune. What other explanation is there of the fact that when men
murder each other, Heaven brings calamity on them? This is the way in which we know that Heaven wants men to
love and benefit each other and does not want them to havte and maltreat each other.Ó (Hughes, p. 46)
ÒAs
a corollary to this categorical imperative of all-embracing love, Mo Ti
denounced wars of aggression, the vice to which his age, as the age before him,
was so prone. He also denounced
extravagant expenditure in the conduct of mourning rites, a practice which the
Confucians, both then and later, greatly encouraged. He also set his face against the luxury in court circles,
involviing as it did the unremunerative use of state funds. His objection was particularly strong
against the art of music, to him a shocking waste of time, money, and
labour. Behind all this lay a
strictly utilitarian mind, which is revealed not only in its rational strength,
but also in its rational limitation, namely its preoccupation with material
prosperity.Ó (Hughes, p. 58.)
Mencius (about 370 to about
290 BC)
Mencius
is in the mainstream of Confucianism, but he downplays the role of the rites
and emphasises that of jen, which is to be extended to all men. Thus he is considered idealistic in
contrast to the more down-to-earth Confucians. The basis for his doctrine, and it needs to be noted that he
is the first Confucian to look for a specific basis of morality (besides the
generic one of Tao), is
that human nature is good. Thus: ÒÕAs
for as what is genuinely in him is concerned, a man is capable of becoming
good,Õ said Mencius. ÔThat is what
I mean by good. As for his
becoming bad, that is not the fault of his native endowment. The heart of compassion is possessed by
all men alike; likewise the heart
of shame, the heart of respect, and the heart of right and wrong. The heart of compassion pertains to
benevolence, the heart of shame to dutifulness, the heart of respect to the
observance of the rites, and the heart of right and wrong to wisdom. Benevolence, dutifulness, observance of
the rites, and wisdom are not welded on to me from the outside; they are in me
originally. Only this has never
dawned on me. That is why it is
said, ÔSeek and you will find it;
let go and you will lose it.Õ There
are cases where one man is twice, five times or countless times better than
another man, but this is only because there are people who fail to make the
best of their native endowment.Ó
(The quote is from Mencius, tr. D. C. Lau, p. 163.)
Four
germs of good action and the corresponding action according to Mencius:
heart
of compassion benevolence
heart
of shame dutifulness
heart
of courtesy and modesty observance
of the rites
heart
of right and wrong wisdom
(Mencius,
p. 83)
The
Eight Shoots, which Tung Chung-Shu atributes to Mencius, are
fidelity
and truth-speaking
all-embracingness
and love
honesty
and generosity
courtesy
and the passion for it.
(Hughes,
p. 303. From Tung Chung-Shu,
the ChÕun ChÕiu Fan Lu (String of Pearls on the Spring and Autumn
Annals), Chapter 35.)
The Chung Yung
(written by followers of
Confucius, about 250 BC)
When
all desires and emotions of a person are satisfied and expressed to the right
degree, the person achieves a harmony within his person which results in good
mental health. Likewise, when all
the desires and feelings of the various ]page break[ types of people who
comprise a society are satisfied and expressed to the right degree, the society
achieves harmony within itself which results in peace and order....
A
well-organized society is a harmonious unity in which people of differing
talents and professions occupy their proper places, perform their proper
functions, and are all equally satisfied and not in conflict with one
another. An ideal world is also a
harmonious unity. The Chung
Yung says: ÔAll things are nurtured together without injuring one
another. All courses are pursued
without collision. This is what
makes Heaven and Earth great.Õ (Ch. 30.) (Fung, pp. 173-4.)
A
description of the moral man from the Chung Yung :
Men
are obtainable on the basis of personality. The cultivation of personality is on the basis of the
Way. The cultivation of the Way is
on the basis of human-heartedness.
[page break[ To be human-hearted is to be a man, and the chief element
in human-heartedness is loving oneÕs parents. So it is with justice: it is to put things right, and the
chief element in it is employing worthy men in public service....
Thus
it is that enlightened men must not fail to cultivate their personalities; and,
having it in mind to do this, they must not fail to serve their parents; and
having it in mind to do this, they must not fail to have knowledge of men; and,
having it in mind to have this knowledge, they must not fail to have knowledge
of Heaven.
There
are five things which concern everybody in the Great Society, as also do the
three means by which these five things are accomplished. To explain, the relationship between
sovereign and subject, between father and son, between husband and wife,
between elder and younger brother, and the equal intercourse between friend and
friend, these five relationships concern everybody in the Great Society. Knowledge, human-heartedness, and
fortitude, these three are the means; for these qualities are the spiritual
power in society as a whole. The means by which this power is made effective is
unity.
Some
people know these relationships by the light of nature. Others know them by learning about them
from a teacher. Others again know
them through hard experience. But
once they all do know them, there is unity. Some people practise these relationships with a natural
ease. Others derive worldly
advantage from their practice of them.
Others again have to force themselves to practise them. But once they all have achieved success
in practising them, there is unity. (This is from section VI of the Chung
Yung as presented in Hughes, pp. 37-38.)
A
list of virtues from Chapter 30 of the Chung Yung, (ÒGenuine LivingÓ
according to the translator):
Only
the most sagely person in the world can unite in himself the quickness,
clarity, breadth, and depth of understanding needed for guiding men, the
magnanimity, generosity, benevolence, and gentleness needed for getting along
with others, the attentiveness, strength, stability, and tenacity needed for
maintaining control, the serenity, seriousness, unwaveringness, and propriety
needed for commanding respect, and the well-informedness, methodicalness,
thoroughness, and penetration needed for exercising sound judgment. (Bahm, pp. 122-123.)
Hsun Tzu (about 300 to about
240 BC)
Hsun
Tzu, a Confucian, held that human nature is evil (citing our evil
inclinations), but that it becomes good in society through the exercise of li,
which to him means social conduct more than ritual. (Fung, pp. 143-7.)
Classical Taoism
It
is well known that Taoism represents what has been called the spiritual or
idealistic side of the Chinese mentality.
Where Confucians refer repeatedly to Òthe way,Ó the Tao, which
lies behind the world of human activity,
the Taoists are concerned entirely with the Tao. According to chapter 12 of the Chuang
Tsu: ÒIn the Great Beginning
there was nothing, and ÔnothingÕ had no name. At the starting point of oneness [viz. the oneness of the
universe] there was only oneness and no concrete form, but life might come into
things. This (stage) can be
described as spiritual power (at work).
The formless then came to have divisions and, what is more, there was
continuity in these. This can be
described as Ôthe lot of the individual; (at work). (With these two powers) there was an uninterrupted stream of
influence at work which made individual things live and brought to pass their
distinctive features. This can be
described as Ôform.ÕÓ (In Hughes, p. 202.) As to our way of understanding things, Fung Yu Lan
paraphrases the Chuang Tzu, ÒWhat is really ÔoneÕ can neither be
discussed nor even conceived. For
as soon as it is thought of and discussed, it becomes something that exists
externally to the person who is doing the thinking and speaking. So its all-embracing unity is thus
lost, it is actually not the real ÔoneÕ at all.Ó (Fung Yu Lan, p. 114.)
This
background leads to the Taoist attitude of looking away from action in the
world and not calling it as right or wrong. The essence of this seems to be expressed in chapter 2 of
the ÒInner ChaptersÓ of the Chuang Tsu, ÒThe equality of all things,Ó or
ChÕi Wu Lun:
Every thing can be a ÒthatÓ, every thing
can be a Ôthis.Ó One man cannot see things as another sees them. One can only know things through
knowing oneself. Therefore it is
said, ÒÕThatÕ comes from Ôthis,Õ and ÔthisÕ comes from ÔthatÕÓ -- which means ÒthatÓ
and ÒthisÓ give birth to one another.
Life arises from death and death from life. What is inappropriate is seen by virtue of what is
appropriate. There is right
because of wrong and wrong because of right. Thus, the sage does not bother with these distinctions but
seeks enlightenment from heaven.
So he sees Òthis,Ó but ÒthisÓ is also Òthat,Ó and ÒthatÓ is also Òthis.Ó ÒThatÓ has elements of right and wrong,
and ÒthisÓ has elements of right
and wrong. Does he still
distinguish between ÒthisÓ and Òthat,Ó or doesnÕt he? When there is no more separation between ÒthisÓ and Òthat,Ó
it is called the still-point of Tao.
At the still-point in the center of the circle one can see the infinite
in all things. Right is infinite;
wrong is also infinite. Therefore
it is said, ÒBehold the light beyond right and wrong.Ó (Feng, Chuang Tsu,
p. 29.)
The
ultimate indifference of our knowledge proposed by Chuang Tsu is, in a way,
skepticism, but whereas the Western Classical Skeptic Sextus Empiricus is
satisfied with ataraxia (tranquillity) without truth, ÒZhuangzi seems to look
for truth and a good life in accord with it.Ó (Kjellberg, .
"Skepticism, truth, and he good life: a comparison of Zhuangzi and Sextus Empiricus.Ó
As
to the life of the sage, Chuang Tsu writes: ÒDo not seek fame. Do not make plans. Do not be absorbed by activities. Do not think that you know. Be aware of all that is and dwell in
the infinite. Wander where there
is no path. Be all that heaven
gave you, but act as though you have received nothing. Be empty, that is all. The mind of a perfect man is like a
mirror. It grasps nothing. It expects nothing. It reflects but does not hold. Therefore, the perfect man can act
without effort.Ó (In chapter 7 of the ÒInner ChaptersÓ, FengÕs translation, p.
159.) Thus the ideal of the Taoist
is to remove himself from the need for action - to live a contemplative life,
but the mainstream of Taoism did not turn away from the affairs of the world. Where necessary Taoists were able to
act in the world as others did, but in so doing they turned their minds away
from the world.
Legalism
Han Fei Tzu (Third century
B.C.)
Although
Arthur Waley agrees with the other sources that Han Fei Tzu is the principal
exponent of what is generally termed the Legalist School, he calls its thinkers
ÒRealistsÓ (Waley, p. 199).
Whatever the name, this school was eminently suited for adoption as the
guiding light of the ChÕin dynasty in the original unification of China (221
B.C.), and for a while it predominated, but only, as it turned out, as a slight
interval in the long history of the Taoist outlook and Confucian principles of
action in China. As Waley
observes, ÒFundamental to Realism was the rejection of private standards of
right and wrong. ÔRightÕ to them
meant Ôwhat the rulers want,Õ ÔwrongÕ meant what the rulers do not want. No individual or school of thought must
be allowed to set up any other standard or ideal.Ó (p. 200) Nevertheless, Waley goes on to note
that to the Realists this description of an ethical standard was made on the
basis of expediency as the rulers saw it, but if the ruler follows the way
of heaven, there is no fundamental discrepancy between this and Taoism or
Confucianism as proposed by either Mo Ti or Hsun Tzu. (p. 200-206)
Waley
compares the three schools:
ÒThe Taoists held that the object of
life should be the cultivation of inner powers; the Confucians, that it should
be the pursuit of Goodness. The
Realists for the most part ignored the individual, and though there are
passages that envisage an ultimate peaceful utopia, their general assumption is
that the object of any society is to dominate other societies.Ó (p. 252.)
Post-classical Philosophers
It
would do a great injustice to Chinese philosophy to assert that it did not
progress after the classical period, that is, after the first century A.D. Nevertheless, it followed the patterns
established in the classical period and did not undergo occasional revolutions
the way Western philosophy did. It
appears that the prime - perhaps the only - reason for this was the adoption of
the classics as the norm of education and the standard of the civil service
exams in a society that perceived little need for change in all that time. The greatest challenge from the outside
was Buddhism, but as a way of thought Buddhism was close enough to Taoism to
fit with the Chinese worldview and sufficiently compatible with Confucianism to
leave intact the social system.
Chu Hsi (1130-1200)
Chu
Hsi is the one later philosopher who so stands out that he should not be
ignored here. He was the master
commentator who gave form to the understanding of the classics until their
function in society came to an end with the first republican government in
1912. Chu Hsi sums up the basic
relationships: ÒÕThe Supreme
Ultimate is simply what is highest of all, beyond which nothing can be. It is the most high, most mystical, and
most abstruse, surpassing everything.
Lest anyone should imagine that the Supreme Ultimate has bodily form,
Lien-Hsi [i.e., Chou Tun-yi] has said of it: ÔThe Ultimateless, and yet also
the Supreme Ultimate.Õ That is, it is in the realm of no things that there is
to be found the highest Li.ÕÓ (Chu-tzu ChÕuan-shu, or Complete
Works of the Master Chu, chuan 49., quoted in Fung, pp. 297-98) From these statements we see that the
position of the Supreme Ultimate in Chu HsiÕs system corresponds to the idea of
the Good or to God in the systems of Plato and Aristotle respectively. ÒThere is one point in Chu HsiÕs system,
however, that makes his Supreme Ultimate more mystical than PlatoÕs idea of the
Good or AristotleÕs God. This is
the fact that, according to Chu Hsi, the Supreme Ultimate is not only the
summation of the Li of the universe as a whole, but is at the same time
immanent in the individual examples of each category of things.Ó (Feng, p. 298.) (Note the notion of Li: ÒFor
every kind of thing there is the Li, which makes it what it ought to be.Ó
p. 297)
Chu
Hsi makes a strong case for human ethics as a matter of manÕs position in the
universe. Thus, ÒIn Chu HsiÕs
Confucian terms, to assume the ethical stance involves appreciating persons as
person-in-context rather than as discrete rational agents. And, to adopt such a notion would be to
conceive of ethics as part and parcel of the fabric of human life rather than as a
heavy-handed theoretical imposition on ÔautonomousÕ selves. Ethics, for Chu Hsi, in theory as well
as in practice delineates the lives of persons-in-context.Ó (Thompson, How to Rejuvenate Ethics:
Suggestions from Chu Hsi,Ó p. 499)
(A companion article to ThompsonÕs is A.S. CuaÕs ÒBetween Commitment and
Realization: Wang Yang-MingÕs Vision of the Universe as a Moral Community.Ó
Wang Yang-Ming (1472-1529), otherwise known as Wang Shou-jen, took issue with
Chu Hsi on important issues of philosophy, but proposed a moral vision very
similar to his.)
Tai Chen (also known as Tai
Tung-YŸan) (1723-77)
As
an example of a ChÕing Dynasty mainstream Confucian of note we have Tai Chen,
who intended to restore the purity of Confucianism from the taint of Taoism and
Buddhism. The essence of TaiÕs
thought on morality can be taken from Fung Yu-lan as follows:
"Man's
knowledge is in its lesser aspects able to encompass the widest ranges of
beauty and ugliness, and in its greater aspects the widest ranges of right and
wrong. It is because this is so
that he is able not only to fulfill his own desires but, through their
extension, the desires of others as well.
The highest morality consists of nothing more than insuring that the
desires of all men reach fulfillment, and their feelings reach expressionÓ (Meaning
of Mencius, 3.105).
Thus
all morality is a product of knowledge. In other words, knowledge becomes
equivalent to morality. It is because man possesses a knowledge denied to other
creatures that he is able to comprehend Principle and moral necessity, and to
conform to them in conduct. He is
able to understand that fellow beings share common feelings and desires, and
therefore to place himself in the position of other men. This is the reason why human nature is
good.
Through
the utmost development of knowledge, is conduct brought into closest harmony
with what is morally necessary, thus permitting the innate potentialities of
the nature to be most nearly realized.
Tai writes:
ÒGoodness
is what is morally necessary, whereas the nature itself is something
natural. To cause it (the nature)
to conform to moral necessity, thereby giving a finished perfection to its
naturalness: this is what is known as developing the natural to its highest
point. In this manner the Way of
Heaven, Earth, man, and creatures is given utmost expressionÕ(ibid., p.
111
ÒHsu*n
Tzu** knew that propriety and righteousness result from the teachings of the
sages, but not that they also derive from the nature. He knew that they consist in the manifestation of what is
morally necessary, but not that this moral necessity represents the highest
ultimate pattern of the natural, to which it gives final perfection. (ibid.,2.92).
Moral
necessity is thus the highest development of the natural. In other words, it gives to the natural
its most perfect development, which is then, says Tai, the highest excellence
of the universe:
For
this reason man is the manifestation of the highest excellence of the universe,
and it is only the sage who completely develops this excellence.Ó(Nature of
Goodness, 2.13). Fung, A History, pp. 662-663 [in the present essay u*=u diaeresis, u**=u upsidedown circumflex].
The
essence of TaiÕs thought on the origin of evil is that human feelings, desires,
and knowledge are all subject to certain failings:
ÒThe
failing in desire is selfishness, the sequel to which is the evil of
greed. The failing in feeling is
one-sidedness, the sequel to which is the sin of perverse
unreasonableness. The failing in
knowledge, is delusion, the sequel to which is the error of fallaciousness. Freed from selfishness, the desires all
correspond to love, propriety, and righteousness. Free from one-sidedness, the feelings are inevitably mild
and easy, even and altruistic.
Freed from delusion, knowledge becomes what is known as (true)
intelligence and sagely wisdomÓ (Meaning of Mencius, 3.105).
Thus
evil arises from certain defects in the feelings, desires, and knowledge. Among these, selfishness (ssu**)
and delusion (pi) are the most notable:
A
manÕs failure to make utmost use of his capacities leads to two calamities,
those of selfishness and delusion....
The best way to get rid of selfishness is to strengthen altruism. The best way to disperse delusion is to
study. (Nature of Goodness, 3.22)
The
way to strengthen altruism (shu), according to Tai, is to measure other
mensÕ desires in terms of oneÕs own.
Selfishness arises when the individual concentrates solely upon his own
desires, while ignoring those of other people. As for knowledge, its relationship to the objects of
knowledge is comparable to that of a light to the objects it illumines: Just as
the light, if obscured, can no longer adequately illumine these objects, so
knowledge, if deluded, can no longer gain correct comprehension of the objects
of knowledge. Thus, for Tai,
knowledge is the equivalent of morality, and its deluding results in the rise
of evil. (Fung, A History, pp. 666-667) [as above, u**=u upsidedown
circumflex] [Not to argue with
Fung about knowledge being the equivalent of morality, it must be observed that
the Chinese philosopher is not separating human mental activities into two
distinct spheres, one of intellection and the other of volition.]
A Summation
Archie
Bahm summarizes much of Chinese thought on the ethical person:
The
Chinese ideal man is harder to locate [than the ideal man of Europe and
India]. In a sense, he is a person
who lacks ideals, or at least idealizes lack of ideals. For when one is fully occupied enjoying
the present, he has no need for attention to future enjoyments. For Lao-Tsu, the ideal man has teh,
the ability to follow his own nature without deviation, or without wanting to
deviate (that is, without having ideals about deviating), from it. In another sense, he has ideals, but
again these are ideals about living naturally. For Confucius, the ideal man tries to embody within himself yi,
jen, li and chih. Yi,
the best way of doing things, is for each thing and person to follow his own
nature without ]page[ deviating.
Since each person is by nature social, his social nature should be
followed in the best way also. Jen, good will, is the willingness that yi,
the best way of doing things, should prevail socially also. Li, appropriate behavior, is the
most efficient way to express oneÕs jen in action. Chih, wisdom,
is achievement of complete willingness to embody yi, jen and li
in oneÕs habits and attitudes.
Since such perfect achievement cannot be expected, chih, etc.,
remain ideals. But, in either
sense, the ideal man willingly accepts his own nature and has no desire to
deviate from natureÕs way. (Bahm, Comparative Philosophy, pp. 60-61.)
A Note on the Golden Rule
The
Golden Rule plays a prominent role in Chinese ethics, but it is not quite the
same as the Golden Rule in Western ethics. The following passages illustrate this:
In
the Analects we find the passage: ÒWhen Chung Kung asked the meaning of jen,
the master said: ÔDo not do to others what you do not wish yourself....ÕÕÕ
(XII, 2.) Again, Confucius is
reported in the Analects as saying: ÒThe man of jen is one who,
desiring to sustain himself, sustains others, and desiring to develop himself,
develops others. To be able from
oneÕs own self to draw a parallel for the treatment of others; that may be
called the way to practise jen.Ó (VI, 28.)
Thus
the practice of jen consists in consideration for others. ÒDesiring to sustain oneself, one
sustains others; desiring to develop oneself, one develops others.Ó In other words: ÒDo to others what you
wish yourself.Ó This is the
positive aspect of the practice, which was called by Confucius chung or Òconscientiousness
to others.Ó And the negative
aspect, which was called by Confucius shu or Òaltruism,Ó is: ÒDo not do
to others what you do not wish yourself.Ó
The practice as a whole is called the principle of chung and shu,
which is Òthe way to practice jen.Ó (Fung, p. 43.)
In
the Great Wisdom (Ta Hsueh) there is a passage which looks like
the Golden Rule, but rather seems to be an exhortation to rulers to treat their
people properly because the people will therefore treat each other
properly. (Bahm, Heart of
Confucius, p. 145.) Here, as
in many passages on the subject of the proper conduct of rulers, the Chinese
books of wisdom do not explain why the goodness of the ruler is so infectious.
The
way Mencius proposes the Golden Rule is:
ÒMencius said, ÔAll the ten thousand things are there in me. There is no greater joy for me than to
find, on self-examination, that I am true to myself. Try your best to treat others as you would wish to be
treated yourself, and you will find that this is the shortest way to
benevolence.Ó Mencius, p.
182 (Book VII, Part A, number 4.)
In its context this seems to mean that true riches do not consist of an
accumulation of things, that they are interior and are to be found if we are
true to ourselves. No Chinese equivalent
is given in the footnotes for Òbenevolence.Ó
Summary and Correlation with
Western Ethics
The
details brought out in the section, ÒEthics in the Various Schools....Ó so
clearly state the implications for human action of the Chinese worldview that a
summary is scarcely needed. Still,
certain points of summation can be made in order to make clear the correlations
between Chinese and Western ethics.
Westerners,
as we have seen, point to ethical actions as those of the whole human person,
who is the ethical subject, and we have seen that Confucius introduced the
ethical subject into Chinese philosophy.
Confucius himself and others after him added specifications about the
position of the ethical subject in the general scheme of things: the harmony of
it with heaven and therefore with society, balance in the middle of extremes,
and human nature either as good in itself or as perfectible in society.
Although
the English word ÒgoodÓ has appeared in various locations above, an explicit
consideration of the Chinese word used for it is in order. The Chinese character translated into
English as ÒgoodÓ is shan,
the most general positive evaluative concept in Chinese. In ethical thought shan has to
do with conforming to the Way (or to oneÕs individual way), but it is not at
all applied to the Way itself.
(Graham, p. 494)
In
view of the meaning of shan it would be inappropriate and perhaps
impossible to institute a general philosophical treatment of the Chinese notion
of good. Clearly it is not to be
construed as a kind of essence which can be described analytically. On the other hand, not wanting to speak
of good solely in terms of ethical norms (i.e., good is said by some to be
whatever promotes the interests of society), we can fall back on the general philosophical
notion of good, "things are
good in so far as they are unified, in so far as they are one," as being
quite fundamental both to the Taoist oneness of the universe and to the
Confucian harmony in society.
Taoism did not pursue to its limit intellectually the notion of oneness
of the universe the way Indian philosophy did, and Confucianism did not look
into as many aspects of human actions as Western philosophy did, but the
original statement does justice to both.
Thus it does not seem to be stretching the meaning of words to contend
that ethical good is a matter of human unifying action as much in the
philosophy of China as it is in that of the West.
In
view of the similarities in fundamentals just mentioned, it does not seem to do
violence to Chinese ethics to analyse them according to the procedure I used in
analysing Western ethics. This
procedure, it is true, arose against a background of Western ethics, but it
transcended the ethics of any particular philosopher. In the present chapter we have already considered the first
steps in the procedure, going from metaphysical worldview to the position of
man in it and the consequent meaning of good action. Now we can look at the norms of ethical action, starting
with the broad divisions of them., i.e., the categories of
antecedent/consequentialist, individual/collective, virtue/intentions, and
cognitive/sentiment, and see how well they apply to Chinese ethics.
First,
there is a very strong , even salient element of consequentialism in Chinese
ethics: all variants of Confucianism are concerned with actions that have
results. The division, however, of
these results into individual and social is arbitrary and useless
in the Confucian way of thinking, in which the good of both is realized harmoniously
or is not realized in either As to
antecedent norms, those of intentions, we have seen in our rapid
survey of the Chinese philosophers, that no opposition is seen between these
and consequent norms.
Moreover, in considering intentions versus virtue as
norms, the distinction appears to
be meaningless to the Confucian point of view, in which jen seems to be
both a principle of action and an attribute of it. (As Angus Graham puts it, ÒWe have suggested that for
Chinese moral philosophizing the good is what the wisest spontaneously
prefer.)(Graham, p. 302) Lastly,
from my readings in Chinese philosophy I infer that making a distinction
between cognitive norms and norms of sentiment would have
appeared to be hair splitting to Confucians, who were more interested in the
unity of cognition and sentiment than in any difference between them..
Taoist
ethics, or the Taoist aspect of Chinese ethics, does not contradict Confucian
ethics, but, as Fung Yu-Lan observes, transcends it by saying, do what you have
to do, but do not put your heart into it.
It would not be correct to say that Taoist ethics is antecedent rather
than, or opposed to, consequent ethics because it does not care about the
outcome. This last clause is
correct, but Taoism is indifferent to the antecedents as well as to the
results.
As to some particular norms, that of
rights does not seems to be found in classical Chinese philosophy,
whereas the closely related one of respect, as distinct from respect for
persons because of their position or standing, is notably present in the
Confucian understanding of the Golden Rule. Although magnanimity in the distribution of benefits is
clearly expected of rulers, I do not see the Western notion of fairness
in the Confucian understanding of ethical interpersonal relationships. I do not judge that the classical
Chinese mind would find value in the Western norm of utility/utilitarianism
because of the Chinese view of the individual and the collective belonging to a
world order which is greater than either.
All classical Chinese ethics, however, is an inner law ethics in
so far as it is built on an unquestioned notion of a fixed human nature with
which we should act in harmony.
In
his introduction to "Liberal Rights or/and Confucian Virtues?" Seung-hwan
Lee assumes that the predominant basis for morality in Western thought is right,
and his purpose is to show how Confucianism presents a corrective to that, and,
conversely, that Confucian ethics need to be complemented by that same notion
of right. Thus,
In
contrast to a liberal, rights-based morality, Confucianism provides a radically
different picture of morality. Being
a morality based on virtue, what Confucianism takes seriously is not rightful
claims or self-assertions, but the virtues of caring and benevolence. What Confucian morality suggests to us
is not that one stand up as a person qua autonomous being, but that one become
a person of excellence (chŸn-tzu).
Unlike the liberal priority of the right over the good, Confucianism
gives priority to becoming a good person over being a right-claimer. (p. 367)
Confucians
maintain that genuine freedom can be achieved not by securing more options, but
by overcoming one's lower desires while spontaneously (as well as
intentionally) internalizing community norms. (p. 369)
Through
the mutual criticisms of the liberal and the traditional Confucian conceptions
of freedom, what is presented before us is not a simple choice between negative
liberty and positive freedom, but a complementary or mutually supportive
relationship between the two senses of freedom. A total freedom includes both maximization of options
and self-realization. A
liberal person needs self-overcoming and the cultivation of his character, and
a Confucian person needs the availability and protection of options in choice
and action. (p. 373)
According
to Confucianism, the field of moral problems is so large and varied that the
narrow subfields picked out by the language of rights fails to include the full
range of significant human experiences.
Confucian virtue-based morality, in contrast to rights-based moralities,
is maximalist in the sense that nothing in human experience is void of
moral significance, and the moral situation is the life of each person in its
entirety. While a rights-based
morality covers only the minimum dimensions of moral actions (that is, right,
permissible, and wrong), Confucian morality covers the maximum range of
human actions as a field for self-cultivation. (p. 374)
[In
conclusion:] Through the mutual criticism of liberalism and Confucianism
concerning the relation between rights and virtues, what is presented before us
is not a simple choice of either rights or virtues, but a
harmonious coordination of rights (as basic requirements of morality) and
virtues (as counsels of moral wisdom).
The minimalist nature of rights-talk and the maximalist aspiration of
virtues, when integrated into one moral schema, will lead to a richer and more
comprehensive appreciation of human development. (p. 376)
A
classical Chinese response to a question raised much later by Western
philosophers, the question of the distinction between ÒisÓ and ÒoughtÓ or
between ÒdoesÓ and Òought to doÓ is based on human actionÕs being a moment in
the more general action of the Tao:
ÒMan is in spontaneous interaction with things, but responds differently
according to the degree of his understanding of their similarities and
contrasts, connexion or isolation. The ÔoughtÕ then finally detaches itself as
an imperative to know how things compare and connect, in particular whether in
connecting they support or conflict with each other, which is to know their
patterns (li) and the Way which unites them all; to know what to do is
to know what one would be moved to do in the sageÕs full knowledge of how
things are related in fact. Once
again then value separates from fact only as the value of wisdom itself.Ó
(Graham, pp. 355-56)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Western
philosophical sources consulted for the purposes of this study
Adler,
Mortimer J. The Idea of Freedom.
Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday & Co., vol. I, 1958; vol II, 1961.
Akaah,
Ishmael P. "Differences in Research Ethics Judgments Between Male and
Female Marketing Professionals." Journal of Business Ethics, Vol 8
(1989), pp. 375-381.
ÒAn
Approach to Ethical Decision Making,Ó
a World Wide Web file of the Markkula Center for Applied Ethics, Santa
Clara University,
Aristotle.
The Nicomachean Ethics, under the title The Ethics of Aristotle,
translated by J. A. K. Thomson.
London: Penguin Books, 1975.
Becker,
Ernst. The Structure of Evil. New York: The Free Press, 1968.
Beauchamp,
Tom L. and James F. Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, New
York: Oxford University Press, 4th ed., 1994.
Bird,
Frederick, and James A. Waters. "The Nature of Managerial Moral
Standards." Journal of
Business Ethics, Vol 6 (1987), pp. 1-13.
Birt,
Robert E. "Identity and the
Question of African Philosophy."
Philosophy East and West, Vol. 41, No. 1, Jan 1991, 95-109.
Black
Hawk. Black Hawk: an
Autobiography. Ed. by Donald Jackson. University of Illinois Press, 1990.
Bourke,
Vernon J. History of Ethics.
Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday & Co., 1968.
Bowie,
Norman. "Business Ethics and Cultural Relativism," in Peter Madsen
and Jay M. Shafritz, eds., Essentials of Business Ethics. New York:
Penguin Books, 1990, pp. 366-382
Brink,
David O., "Pursuing perfections," Times Literary Supplement,
June 24, 1994, a review of Thomas Hurka, Perfectionism
Brody,
Eugene B. Biomedical Technology and Human Rights. Paris: UNESCO, 1993.
UCSC.
Bulger,
Ruth Ellen, Elizabeth Meyer Bobby, and Harvey V. Fineberg, eds. SocietyÕs
Choices. Social and Ethical Decision Making in Biomedicine. Washington,
D.C.: National Academy Press, 1995.
Cadoux,
A. T. "The Implications of the Golden Rule." International Journal
of Ethics, XXII (1912) 272-287.
Callicott,
J. Baird. EarthÕs Insights: A Survey of Ecological Ethics from the
Mediterranean Basin to the Australian Outback. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press: 1994.
Cavalier,
Robert J. Ethics in the History of Western Philosophy. London: The
MacMillan Press Ltd. 1989.
Coles,
Robert. The Moral Life of Children. 1986. 302 pp. Atlantic Monthly
Press, Boston/New York.
Cooper,
David E. World Philosophies An
Historical Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell, 1996.
Copleston,
Frederick. A History of
Philosophy. Volumes 1 through
9, New York, Image Books, 1993-94.
Cranston,
Maurice. What Are Human Rights? New York: Basic Books, 1962.
Dallmayr, Fred. ÒÕAsian ValuesÕ and Global RightsÓ, Philosophy East and West, Vol.
52, No. 2, April, 2002, pp. 173-189.
Deeken,
Alfons. Process & Permanence in Ethics: Max SchelerÕs Moral Philosophy.
New York: Paulist Press, 1974.
Donnelly,
Jack. Universal Human Rights in
Theory and Practice. Ithaca
and London, Cornell University Press, 1989.
Edel,
Abraham. "The Concept of Value and Its Travels in Twentieth-Century
America," in Values and Value Theory in Twentieth-Century America,
Murray G. Murphey and Ivar Berg
Essays in Honor of Elizabeth Flower. Philadelphia, Temple
University Press, 1988.
Edel,
May and Abraham Edel. Anthropology
and Ethics. Revised ed. Cleveland: The Press of Case Western Reserve
University, 1968
Encyclopedia
of Philosophy
Firth,
Raymond. Elements of Social Organization. New York: Philosophical
Library, 1951.
Fleischacker,
Samuel. The Ethics of Culture. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994.
Fortes,
Meyer. Religion, morality and
the person: Essays on the Tallensi religion. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1987.
French,
Peter. Collective and Corporate
Responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press, 1984.
Fustel
de Coulanges, Numa Denis. The
Ancient City. Garden City, New York: Doubleday & Co., 1956.
Goethe,
Johann, Faust
Hale,
John. The Civilization of
Europe in the Renaissance. New York: Atheneum, 1994.
Heidegger,
Martin. Being and Time. New York: Harper & Row, 1962.
Heidegger,
Martin. On Time and Being. New York: Harper & Row, 1972.
Heller,
Agnes. General Ethics.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990.
Hertzler,
J.O. "On Golden Rules." in The International Journal of Ethics,
44, (1934) 418-436.
Hindley,
Geoffrey. The Book of Magna
Carta. London: Constable, 1990.
Hofstadter,
Richard. Anti-intellectualism
in American Life. New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1970.
Holmes,
Stephen & Cass Sunstein, The Cost of Rights, New York: Norton, 1999.
Homer, The Odyssey
Hume,
Robert Ernest. The World's Living Religions. New York: Charles
Scribner's Sons, 1929.
James,
William. The Varieties of Religious Experience. New York: Penguin Books, 1982.
Jaspers,
Karl. The Question of German Guilt. New York: The Dial Press, 1947.
Johnson,
Mark. Moral Imagination:
Implication of Cognitive Science for Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Jonsen,
Albert R. The New Medicine and
the Old Ethics. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1990
Joseph,
Lawrence E. Gaia: The Growth of an Idea. New York: St. Martin's Press,
1990.
Kafka,
Franz , The Metamorphosis
Kjellberg,
Paul. "Skepticism, truth, and
he good life: a comparison of Zhuangzi
and Sextus Empiricus." Philosophy
East & West, Vol 44, No. 1, Jan 1994, 111-133.
Kohlberg,
Lawrence. "Moral stages and moralization. The cognitive-developmental
approach," in Thomas Lickona ed., Moral development and behavior. Theory, research and social issues.
New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1976.
Kohlberg,
Lawrence, Charles Levine, and Alexandra Hewer. Moral Stages: A Current
Formulation and a Response to Critics. Basel: S. Karger, 1983.
Laszlo,
Ervin. Introduction to Systems Philosophy. New York: Gordon and Breach, 1972.
Lawson,
Hilary. Closure A Story of
Everything. London and New York:
Routledge, 1991.
Leopold,
Aldo. A Sand County
Almanac. With Essays on
Conservations from Round River.
New York: Ballantine Books, 1970.
Macbeath,
Alexander. Experiments in Living. A study of the nature and foundation of
ethics or morals in the light of recent work in social anthropology. London: Macmillan & Co., 1952.
Machiavelli,
NiccoloÕ. The Prince and the Discourses. New York: The Modern Library,
Random House, 1950.
Martin,
Gottfried. General Metaphysics
Its Problems and Its Method. Transl. by Daniel O'Connor. London:
George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1968.
Maslow,
Abraham. Motivation and
Personality. New York: Harper & Brothers, 2nd Ed, 1970.
Masters,
Edgar Lee, Spoon River
Anthology
May,
Larry. The Morality of Groups: Collective Responsibility, Group-Based Harm,
and Corporate Rights. Notre
Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987.
May,
Larry, and Stacey Hoffman, Eds. Collective Responsibility Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical
and Applied Ethics. Savage,
Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991.
Mill,
John Stuart. Utilitarianism,
1863.
Murdoch,
Iris. Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals. London: Chatto & Windus, 1992.
Nozick,
Robert. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1981.
Nussbaum,
Martha. Love's Knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Otto,
Rudolf. The Idea of the Holy. London: Oxford University Press,
reprint of 1968.
Piaget,
Jean. The Moral Judgment of the Child. Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press, 1948.
Paine,
Thomas. The Rights of Man, 1792 in Moncure Daniel Conway, Ed. The
Writings of Thomas Paine, Vol II. New York: AMS Press, 1967.
Pincoffs,
Edmund L. Quandaries and Virtues.
Lawrence, Kansas: University Press of Kansas, 1986.
PresidentÕs
Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and
Behavioral Research. Deciding to Forego Life-Sustaining Treatment.
Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1983.
Rawls,
John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press, 1971.
Regan,
Tom. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 1983.
Ricoeur,
Paul. Freedom and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1966.
Rousseau,
Jean-Jacques. The Social Contract. Penguin Books, 1974.
Sahtouris,
Elisabet. Gaia: The Human
Journey From Chaos to Cosmos. New York: Simon & Schuster Pocket Books,
1989.
Scharfstein,
Ben-Ami. Ineffability.
Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1993.
Scheler,
Max. Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1973.
Shelp,
Earl E. ed. Beneficence and Health Care. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1982.
Singer,
Marcus. "The Golden Rule." Philosophy, XXXVIII (1963),
292-314.
Singer,
Peter. Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Slote,
Michael. From Morality to Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press,
1992.
Snell,
Bruno. The Discovery of the Mind in Greek Philosophy and Literature,
transl by T.G.Rosenmeyer. New York: Dover Publications, 1982
Stone,
Christopher, "Should Trees Have Standing?" in the Southern
California Law Review, Vol. 45, 1972.
Also his book by the same title,
Los Altos CA: Wm. Kaufmann, Inc., 1974.
Stroud,
Barry, Review of Problems in Philosophy by Colin McGinn in Times
Literary Supplement, Feb. 25, 1994, N. 4743, p. 8.
Thompson,
Andrew. Guide to Ethical Practice in Psychotherapy. New York: John Wiley
and Sons, 1990. UCSC....
United
Nations, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1948
Veatch,
Robert M. A Theory of Medical
Ethics. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1981.
Velasquez,
Manuel. Business Ethics: Concepts and Cases. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 3rd edition, 1992.
Walhout,
Donald. The Good and the Realm of Values. Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1978.
Wallace,
James D. Virtues and Vices. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1978.
Wattles,
Jeffrey. The Golden Rule. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Werhane,
Patricia. Persons, Rights, & Corporations. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall, 1985.
Whitehead,
Alfred North. Process and Reality. New York: Harper and Row, 1960.
Whorf,
Benjamin. Language, Thought and
Reality. selected writings of
Benjamin Lee Whorf, ed. by John B. Carroll. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT
Press, 1956.
Wood,
Robert P. Ed. The Future of Metaphysics. Chicago: Quadrangle Books,
1970.
Indian
philosophical sources consulted for the purposes of this study
Basham,
Arthur L. The Origins and
Development of Classical Hinduism.
Boston: Beacon Press, 1989.
Cooper,
David. World Philosophies. An Historical Introduction. Oxford UK and Cambridge MA: Blackwell
Publishers, 1996.
Dasgupta,
Surama. Development of Moral
Philosophy in India. New York:
Frederick Ungar Publ. Co., 1965.
Penguin
Classic editions:
ö The
Rig Veda. Translated and edited by Wendy Doniger OÕFlaherty. Penguin
Books,1981.
ö The
Upanishads. Translated and edited by Juan MascaroÕ. Penguin Books, 1965.
ö The
Bhagavad Gita. Translated and
edited by Juan MascaroÕ. Penguin Books, 1962.
Potter,
Karl H. Presuppositions of IndiaÕs Philosophies. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1963.
Radhakrishnan,
Sarvepalli et al. History of Philosophy: Eastern and Western. Volume 1.
London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1952.
Radhakrishnan,
S. and Muirhead, J.H. Editors. Contemporary Indian Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin, Third
impression, 1958.
Sharma,
I.C. Ethical Philosophies of India. Lincoln, Nebraska: Johnsen Publ. Co.: 1965.
Tigunait,
Pandit R. Seven Systems of Indian Philosophy. Honesdale, Pennsylvania:
Himalayan Institute Press, 1983.
Works examined for an
understanding of the Sanskrit language:
Bhandarkar,
Ramkrishna Gopal. First Book of
Sanskrit. Bombay: Gopal
Narayen & Co., 27th ed., 1923.
Burrow, T. The Sanskrit Language. London: Faber and Faber. New and revised edition, 1973.
Chinese
philosophical sources consulted for the purposes of this study
Bahm,
Archie J. Comparative
Philosophy: Western, Indian, and Chinese Philosophies Compared. Albuquerque, New Mexico: World Books,
1977.
Bahm,
Archie J. The Heart of
Confucius . Interpretations of Genuine Living and Great Wisdom. New York: Harper & Row, Perennial
Library, 1971.
Benesch,
Walter. An Introduction to
Comparative Philosophy: A Travel Guide to Philosophical Space. New York: St. MartinÕs Press, Inc.,
1997.
Blakney,
R. B.: The Way of Life
Lao Tzu: New York: The New American Library, Mentor Books, 1955.
Chung-ying
Cheng. New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy, Albany:
State University of New York Press, 1991.
Cooper,
David E. World Philosophies: An Historical Introduction. Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers, 1996.
Cua,
A. S., ÒBetween Commitment and Realization: Wang Yang-MingÕs Vision of the
Universe as a Moral Community.Ó Philosophy
East and West, Vol. 43, No. 4, Oct. 1993, 611-647
Feng,
Gia-Fu, and Jane English. Chuang Tsu
Inner Chapters. New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 1974.
Fung
Yu-lan, A History of Chinese
Philosophy Vol. II, "The Period of Classical Learning." Tran. by Derk Bodde. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1953.
Fung
Yu-Lan. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. New York, etc.: The Free
Press, a division of Simon and Schuster, reprint of 1997; first printing 1948.
Graham,
Angus C. Disputers of the Tao.
Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. La Salle, Illinois: Open
Court Publ. Co., 1989.
Hughes,
E. R. Chinese Philosophy in Classical Times. London: Dent, EverymanÕs Library, 1942.
Hansen,
Chad. Language and Logic in Ancient China. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1983.
Jiyuan
Yu. ÒVirtue: Confucius and Aristotle.Ó In Philosophy East and West, Vol.
48, No. 2, April 1998, pp. 323-347.
Kjellberg,
Paul. "Skepticism, truth, and
he good life: a comparison of
Zhuangzi and Sextus Empiricus."
Philosophy East and West, Vol 44, No. 1, Jan 1994, 111-133.
Lau,
D. C. Mencius.
Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England, Penguin Books, 1970.
Mair,
Victor H. Tao Te Ching The
Classic Book of Integrity and the Way
Lao Tzu. New York:
Bantam Books, 1990.
Mou,
Bo. "The Structure of the
Chinese Language and Ontological Insights: A Collective-Noun Hypothesis," Philosophy
East and West, Vol. 4, No. 1, Jan. 1999, 45-62.
Seung-hwan
Lee. "Liberal Rights or/and Confucian
Virtues?" Philosophy East
and West, Vol. 46, No. 3, July
1996, 367-379.
Thompson,
Kirill Ole, ÒHow to Rejuvenate Ethics: Suggestions from Chu Hsi,Ó Philosophy
East and West, Vol 41, No. 4, Oct. 1991, 493-513.
Waley,
Arthur. Three Ways of Thought in Ancient China. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd,
1939.
Works examined to gain an
understanding of the Chinese language:
Elementary
Chinese. (author not named in
English). Beijing: Shan Wu Yiu Shu Kuan, Part I, 1971 and Part II, 1972
Forrest,
R. A. D. The Chinese Language.
London: Faber and Faber limited, 1948.
Henne,
Henry, Ole Bjorn Rongen, Lars Jul Hansen. A Handbook on Chinese Language
Structure. Oslo and other locations: Scandinavian University Books, 1977.